Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 15 (3):313-317 (2018)
Authors |
|
Abstract |
Aulisio and Arora argue that the moral significance of value imposition explains the moral distinction between traditional conscientious objection and non-traditional conscientious objection. The former objects to directly performing actions, whereas the latter objects to indirectly assisting actions on the grounds that indirectly assisting makes the actor morally complicit. Examples of non-traditional conscientious objection include objections to the duty to refer. Typically, we expect physicians who object to a practice to refer, but the non-traditional conscientious objector physician refuses to refer. Aulisio and Arora argue that physicians have a duty to refer because refusing to do so violates the patient’s values. While we agree with Aulisio and Arora’s conclusions, we argue value imposition cannot adequately explain the moral difference between traditional conscientious objection and non-traditional conscientious objection. Treating autonomy as the freedom to live in accordance with one’s values, as Aulisio and Arora do, is a departure from traditional liberal conceptions of autonomy and consequently fails to explain the moral difference between the two kinds of objection. We outline how a traditional liberal understanding of autonomy would help in this regard, and we make two additional arguments—one that maintains that non-traditional conscientious objection undermines society’s autonomy, and another that maintains that it undermines the physician-patient relationship—to establish why physicians have a duty to refer.
|
Keywords | No keywords specified (fix it) |
Categories | (categorize this paper) |
ISBN(s) | |
DOI | 10.1007/s11673-018-9854-9 |
Options |
![]() ![]() ![]() ![]() |
Download options
References found in this work BETA
Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government.Philip Pettit (ed.) - 1997 - Oxford University Press.
Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government.Philip Pettit - 1999 - Philosophical Quarterly 49 (196):415-419.
View all 8 references / Add more references
Citations of this work BETA
Responding to Religious Patients: Why Physicians Have No Business Doing Theology.Jake Greenblum & Ryan K. Hubbard - 2019 - Journal of Medical Ethics 45 (11):705-710.
In Defence of Forgetting Evil: A Reply to Pilkington on Conscientious Objection.Jake Greenblum & T. J. Kasperbauer - 2021 - Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 18 (1):189-191.
Embedded Journalists or Empirical Critics? The Nature of The “Gaze” in Bioethics.Michael A. Ashby & Bronwen Morrell - 2018 - Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 15 (3):305-307.
Conscience Dissenters and Disagreement: Professions are Only as Good as Their Practitioners.Bryan C. Pilkington - 2021 - HEC Forum 33 (3):233-245.
Remember Evil: Remaining Assumptions In Autonomy-Based Accounts Of Conscience Protection.Bryan C. Pilkington - 2019 - Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 16 (4):483-488.
View all 9 citations / Add more citations
Similar books and articles
The Foundations of Conscientious Objection: Against Freedom and Autonomy.Yossi Nehushtan & John Danaher - 2018 - Jurisprudence 9 (3):541-565.
Conscientious Objection and Health Care: A Reply to Bernard Dickens.C. Kaczor - 2012 - Christian Bioethics 18 (1):59-71.
The Christian Physician in the Non-Christian Institution: Objections of Conscience and Physician Value Neutrality.J. F. Peppin - 1997 - Christian Bioethics 3 (1):39-54.
Conscientious Objection: A Morally Insupportable Misuse of Authority.Arianne Shahvisi - 2018 - Clinical Ethics 13 (2):82-87.
Speak No Evil? Conscience and the Duty to Inform, Refer or Transfer Care.Mark P. Aulisio & Kavita Shah Arora - 2014 - HEC Forum 26 (3):257-266.
Referral in the Wake of Conscientious Objection to Abortion.Carolyn McLeod - 2008 - Hypatia 23 (4):30-47.
Conscientious Objection, Professional Duty and Compromise: A Response to Savulescu and Schuklenk.Jonathan A. Hughes - 2018 - Bioethics 32 (2):126-131.
Is It Ethical for a General Practitioner to Claim a Conscientious Objection When Asked to Refer for Abortion?J. W. Gerrard - 2009 - Journal of Medical Ethics 35 (10):599-602.
Public Reason and the Limited Right to Conscientious Objection: A Response to Magelssen.Jake Greenblum - 2018 - Journal of Medical Ethics 44 (3):206-209.
Do No Evil: Unnoticed Assumptions in Accounts of Conscience Protection.Bryan C. Pilkington - 2016 - HEC Forum 28 (1):1-10.
When Should Conscientious Objection Be Accepted.Morten Magelssen - 2012 - Journal of Medical Ethics 38 (1):18-21.
Conscientious Objection to Referrals for Abortion: Pragmatic Solution or Threat to Women’s Rights?Eva M. K. Nordberg, Helge Skirbekk & Morten Magelssen - 2014 - BMC Medical Ethics 15 (1):15.
Testing Conscientious Objection by the Norm of Medicine.Toni C. Saad & Gregory Jackson - 2018 - Clinical Ethics 13 (1):9-16.
Conscientious Refusals to Refer: Findings From a National Physician Survey.M. P. Combs, R. M. Antiel, J. C. Tilburt, P. S. Mueller & F. A. Curlin - 2011 - Journal of Medical Ethics 37 (7):397-401.
Civic Conscience, Selective Conscientious Objection and Lack of Choice.Yossi Nehushtan - 2017 - Ratio Juris 30 (4):433-450.
Analytics
Added to PP index
2018-05-22
Total views
13 ( #772,731 of 2,520,404 )
Recent downloads (6 months)
2 ( #270,555 of 2,520,404 )
2018-05-22
Total views
13 ( #772,731 of 2,520,404 )
Recent downloads (6 months)
2 ( #270,555 of 2,520,404 )
How can I increase my downloads?
Downloads