Predelli on Fictional Discourse

Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 80 (1):83-94 (2022)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

John Searle argues that fictions are constituted by mere pretense—by the simulation of representational activities like assertions, without any further representational aim. They are not the result of sui generis, dedicated speech acts of a specific kind, on a par with assertion. The view had earlier many defenders, and still has some. Stefano Predelli enlists considerations derived from Searle in support of his radical fictionalism. This is the view that a sentence of fictional discourse including a prima facie empty fictional name like “Emma Woodhouse” in fact “is not a sentence, and it encodes no proposition whatsoever.” His argument is broadly abductive; he claims that this view affords compelling explanations of features of fictions he finds well-established, among them that fictions without explicit narrators nonetheless have covert ones. Here I take up his arguments, in defense of the dedicated speech act view. I thus address pressing issues about the status of fictional names and the nature and ubiquity of narrators in fictions.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,164

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Speaking of Fictional Characters.Amie L. Thomasson - 2003 - Dialectica 57 (2):205-223.
Speaking of fictional characters.Amie L. Thomasson - 2003 - Dialectica 57 (2):205–223.
How I Stopped Worrying and Started Loving 'Sherlock Holmes': A Reply to Garcia-Carpintero.Heidi Savage - 2020 - Teorema: International Journal of Philosophy 1 (XXXIX):105-134.
Semantics of fictional terms.Manuel García-Carpintero - 2019 - Teorema: International Journal of Philosophy 38 (2):73-100.
Fictional States of Affairs and Literary Discourse.Peter McCormick - 1983 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 19 (1):163-178.
Fictional States of Affairs and Literary Discourse.Peter McCormick - 1983 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 19 (1):163-178.
Fictional characters.Stacie Friend - 2007 - Philosophy Compass 2 (2):141–156.
Free Indirect Discourse in Non-Fiction.Andreas Stokke - 2021 - Frontiers in Communication 5 (606616).
Vergil and dido.Jérôme Pelletier - 2003 - Dialectica 57 (2):191–203.
The Worlds of Art and the World.Peter McCormick - 1983 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 19:163-178.
Fictional names and individual concepts.Andreas Stokke - 2020 - Synthese 198 (8):7829-7859.

Analytics

Added to PP
2022-04-08

Downloads
28 (#536,385)

6 months
13 (#161,691)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Manuel García-Carpintero
Universitat de Barcelona

Citations of this work

The semantics of fiction.Manuel García-Carpintero - 2023 - Mind and Language 38 (2):604-618.
‘Truth in Fiction’ Reprised.Manuel García-Carpintero - 2022 - British Journal of Aesthetics 62 (2):307-324.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Reference and Existence: The John Locke Lectures.Saul A. Kripke - 2013 - New York: Oxford University Press.
A puzzle about belief.Saul A. Kripke - 1979 - In A. Margalit (ed.), Meaning and Use. Reidel. pp. 239--83.
The Nature of Fiction.Gregory Currie - 1990 - Cambridge University Press.
Truth in fiction.David K. Lewis - 1978 - American Philosophical Quarterly 15 (1):37–46.

View all 62 references / Add more references