Defending Millian Theories

Mind 107 (428):703-728 (1998)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

In this article I offer a three-pronged defense of Millian theories, all of which share the rough idea that all there is to a proper name is its referent, so it has no additional sense. I first give what I believe to be the first correct analysis of Kripke’s puzzle and its anti-Fregean lessons. The main lesson is that the Fregean’s arguments against Millianism and for the existence of semantically relevant senses (that is, individuative elements of propositions or belief contents that are sensitive to our varying personal conceptions of the referents of those elements) are viciously circular. Thus, the Fregean must give new arguments for her central claims. Second, I offer an original, positive argument for the Millian idea that the thoughts that Cicero was bald and that Tully was bald are identical. Incredibly, the argument appeals to nothing but highly intuitive, pre-theoretical principles regarding folk psychological usage—traditionally the source of Fregean intuitions. Third, I examine one of the most important recent papers on Kripke’s puzzle, that by David Sosa (1996). Sosa claims to have found a way to turn the tables on Kripke’s puzzle by using it to argue against Millian theories. I argue that Sosa’s argument on behalf of the Fregean is question-begging. I conclude that Millian theories can be seriously defended without any use of theoretical constructs such as guises or Russellian propositions, and Fregeans need to start over arguing for their theory’s central claims.

Similar books and articles

Understanding Kripke's puzzles about belief.Michael McGlone - 2009 - Philosophy Compass 4 (3):487-514.
Millian descriptivism.Ben Caplan - 2007 - Philosophical Studies 133 (2):181-198.
Arguing for Frege's Fundamental Principle.Bryan Frances - 1998 - Mind and Language 13 (3):341–346.
Understanding proper names.Michael McKinsey - 2010 - Linguistics and Philosophy 33 (4):325-354.
Contradictory Belief and Epistemic Closure Principles.Bryan Frances - 1999 - Mind and Language 14 (2):203–226.
Los nombres y la referencia: semantica y metasemantica.Robert Stalnaker - 1998 - Teorema: International Journal of Philosophy 17 (1):7-19.
Paderewski Variations.R. Mark Sainsbury - 2010 - Dialectica 64 (4):483-502.

Analytics

Added to PP
2009-01-28

Downloads
723 (#21,363)

6 months
113 (#32,617)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Citations of this work

Attitude Reports: Do You Mind the Gap?Berit Brogaard - 2008 - Philosophy Compass 3 (1):93-118.
One Dogma of Millianism.Derek Ball & Bryan Pickel - 2014 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 88 (1):70-92.
A Test for Theories of Belief Ascription.B. Frances - 2002 - Analysis 62 (2):116-125.
Disquotation and Substitutivity.Bryan Frances - 2000 - Mind 109 (435):519-25.

View all 8 citations / Add more citations

References found in this work

Frege’s Puzzle (2nd edition).Nathan U. Salmon - 1986 - Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Publishing Company.
A puzzle about belief.Saul A. Kripke - 1979 - In A. Margalit (ed.), Meaning and Use. Reidel. pp. 239--83.
Do belief reports report beliefs?Kent Bach - 1997 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 78 (3):215-241.
The structure of content.Colin McGinn - 1982 - In Andrew Woodfield (ed.), Thought And Object: Essays On Intentionality. New York: Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Cognitive science and the twin-earth problem.Jerry A. Fodor - 1982 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 23 (April):98-118.

View all 16 references / Add more references