On a recent critique of complementarity: Part II

Philosophy of Science 36 (1):82-105 (1969)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

“Bohr was primarily a philosopher, not a physicist, but he understood that natural philosophy... carries weight only if its every detail can be subjected to the... test of experiment”. As a result his approach differed from that of the school-philosophers whom he regarded with a somewhat “sceptical attitude, to say the least” and whose lack of interest in “the important viewpoint which had emerged during the development of atomic physics” he noticed with regret. But it also differed, and to a considerable degree, from the spirit of what Professor T. S. Kuhn has called a “normal science.” Looking at Bohr's method of research we see that technical problems, however remote, are always related to a philosophical point of view; they are never treated as “tiny puzzles” whose solution is valuable in itself, even if one has not the faintest idea what it means, and where it leads: “For me” Bohr writes to Sommerfeld in 1922 “[the quantum theory] is not a matter for petty didactic details, but a serious attempt to reach... an inner coherence.” Emphasis is put on matters of principle and minor discrepancies, or “puzzles” in the sense of Kuhn, instead of being deemphasized, and assimilated to the older paradigm, are turned into fundamental difficulties by looking at them from a new direction, and by testing their background “in its furthest consequences by exaggeration”. A noteworthy example of Bohr's “non-normal” and rather metaphysical approach to physics is his scepticism in the face of the success of his own atomic model.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,322

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

On a recent critique of complementarity: Part I.Paul K. Feyerabend - 1968 - Philosophy of Science 35 (4):309-331.
Schrödinger's interpretation of quantum mechanics and the relevance of Bohr's experimental critique.Slobodan Perovic - 2006 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 37 (2):275-297.
Analogues of quantum complementarity in the theory of automata - a prolegomenon to the philosophy of quantum mechanics.T. Acton, S. Caffrey, S. Dunn, P. Vinson & K. Svozil - 1998 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 29 (1):61-80.
The philosophy of Niels Bohr: the framework of complementarity.Henry J. Folse - 1985 - New York, N.Y.: Sole distributors for the U.S.A. and Canada, Elsevier Science Pub. Co..
On complementarity and causal isomorphism.Douglas M. Snyder - 1988 - Journal of Mind and Behavior 9 (1):1-4.

Analytics

Added to PP
2009-01-28

Downloads
97 (#174,177)

6 months
28 (#106,370)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Citations of this work

Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics.Jan Faye - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Was Feyerabend an anarchist? The structure(s) of ‘anything goes’.Jamie Shaw - 2017 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 64:11-21.
Constructing the myth of the copenhagen interpretation.Kristian Camilleri - 2009 - Perspectives on Science 17 (1):pp. 26-57.

View all 19 citations / Add more citations

References found in this work

Measurements and quantum states: Part I.Henry Margenau - 1963 - Philosophy of Science 30 (1):1-16.
The quantum theoretical concept of measurement.John L. McKnight - 1957 - Philosophy of Science 24 (4):321-330.
Patterns of discovery.P. K. Feyerabend - 1960 - Philosophical Review 69 (2):247-252.

Add more references