Names Are Predicates

Philosophical Review 124 (1):59-117 (2015)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

One reason to think that names have a predicate-type semantic value is that they naturally occur in count-noun positions: ‘The Michaels in my building both lost their keys’; ‘I know one incredibly sharp Cecil and one that's incredibly dull’. Predicativism is the view that names uniformly occur as predicates. Predicativism flies in the face of the widely accepted view that names in argument position are referential, whether that be Millian Referentialism, direct-reference theories, or even Fregean Descriptivism. But names are predicates in all of their occurrences; they are predicates that are true of their bearers. When a name appears as a bare singular in argument position, it really occupies the predicate position of what in this essay is called a denuded definite description: a definite description with an unpronounced definite article. Sloat provided good evidence for this. The definite article is sometimes pronounced with names in the singular: ‘The Ivan we all love doesn't feel well’. Sloat proposed a disjunctive generalization of when the definite article must be pronounced with a singular name. This essay shows that by slightly revising Sloat's generalization, we arrive at a simple, nondisjunctive, syntactic rule that governs the overt appearance of the definite article with singular names. But Ivan does not necessarily bear the name ‘Ivan’, so one might worry that the sentence “Ivan might not have had ‘Ivan’ as a name” would incorrectly be predicted false. This essay shows that Predicativism does not have this consequence by showing that incomplete definite descriptions in general and incomplete denuded descriptions, such as ‘Øthe Ivan’, in particular are rigid designators

Other Versions

No versions found

Similar books and articles

The complex lives of proper names.Eno Agolli - 2023 - Linguistics and Philosophy 46 (6):1393-1439.
‘The’ Problem for the-Predicativism.Robin Jeshion - 2017 - Philosophical Review 126 (2):219-240.
Names as Predicates.Sarah Sawyer - 2021 - In Heimir Geirsson & Stephen Biggs (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of Linguistic Reference. New York: Routledge. pp. 198-212.
Against predicativism about names.Jeonggyu Lee - 2020 - Philosophical Studies 177 (1):243-261.
Names and predicates.Eddy M. Zemach - 1981 - Philosophia 10 (3-4):217-223.
Names in strange places.Aidan Gray - 2017 - Linguistics and Philosophy 40 (5):429-472.
The Predicative Predicament.Anders J. Schoubye - 2016 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 96 (3):571-595.

Analytics

Added to PP
2010-11-03

Downloads
3,853 (#2,049)

6 months
326 (#5,655)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Delia Fara
Last affiliation: Princeton University

Citations of this work

Semantics without semantic content.Daniel W. Harris - 2020 - Mind and Language 37 (3):304-328.
Theories of Meaning.Jeff Speaks - forthcoming - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Type-Ambiguous Names.Anders J. Schoubye - 2017 - Mind 126 (503):715-767.
Counteridenticals.Alexander W. Kocurek - 2018 - The Philosophical Review 127 (3):323-369.

View all 96 citations / Add more citations

References found in this work

Naming and Necessity.Saul Kripke - 1980 - Philosophy 56 (217):431-433.
On Denoting.Bertrand Russell - 1905 - Mind 14 (56):479-493.
Naming and Necessity.Saul Kripke - 1980 - Critica 17 (49):69-71.
Principles of mathematics.Bertrand Russell - 1931 - New York,: W.W. Norton & Company.
Word and Object.Willard Van Orman Quine - 1960 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 17 (2):278-279.

View all 71 references / Add more references