The Reflexive Turn, the Linguistic Turn, and the Pragmatic Outcome

The Monist 53 (4):588-605 (1969)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

One of the important philosophical advantages stemming from study of the historical development of philosophical movements and traditions is the insight that comes from observing the logical out-working of a set of ideas over a period of time that far exceeds the lifetime of any individual thinker. An Aristotle or a Hegel may develop a philosophical mode of thought in an almost unbelievably comprehensive way, but no individual can grasp all the implications and ramifications of his philosophical vision, no matter how monumental his powers may be. Many individuals, however, working over many years within the same framework of ideas can accomplish what no one of them alone could achieve. It is often said that philosophy is not an experimental science, and, in an obvious sense, this is true. But it is not entirely true. We can view the history of a tradition like Platonism, for example, or Augustinianism, as a vast experiment made by many thinkers with a set of ideas in which each thinker, building on what has gone before, seeks to develop further the basic premises of the position, proposing new logical alternatives, correcting errors, meeting objections, discovering further implications, and consolidating the results. In the case of a profound tradition, nothing less than this extended historical dialectic of ideas suffices to make plain what the basic position implies. Moreover, since climates of opinion change, the proponents of a given view will find that, in the course of time, new opponents appear, raising questions and posing problems that could not easily have been envisaged by the thinker who started the tradition. Sometimes these objections prove fatal and the tradition comes to an end; sometimes the objections are successfully overcome and the position finds new life and a more viable form of expression. The history of a tradition, therefore, is an indispensable resource for philosophical understanding.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,219

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Zur bewertung der pragmatischen erklärungsmodelle.András Kertész - 1988 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 19 (2):239-251.
Philosophy, linguistic analysis, and linguistics.Karel Mom - 2011 - In Chr Krijnen & K. W. Zeidler (eds.), Gegenstandsbestimmung und Selbstgestaltung. Königshausen & Neumann. pp. 243-261.
Semanticity: Which way to turn?Andrew Sneddon - 2002 - Philosophia 29 (1-4):211-239.
Abulafia's Secrets of the Guide: A linguistic Turn: A linguistic Turn.Moshe Idel - 1998 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 4:495-528.
The Principles of Analytical Philosophy.Gianluigi Oliveri - 1988 - Dissertation, University of Oxford (United Kingdom)
Pictorial turn and Linguistic turn.Karlheinz Lüdeking - 2006 - Nordic Journal of Aesthetics 18 (33-34).

Analytics

Added to PP
2017-02-15

Downloads
15 (#893,994)

6 months
5 (#544,079)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

No references found.

Add more references