Mathematics, ethics and purism: an application of MacIntyre’s virtue theory

Synthese 199 (1-2):3137-3167 (2020)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

A traditional problem of ethics in mathematics is the denial of social responsibility. Pure mathematics is viewed as neutral and value free, and therefore free of ethical responsibility. Applications of mathematics are seen as employing a neutral set of tools which, of themselves, are free from social responsibility. However, mathematicians are convinced they know what constitutes good mathematics. Furthermore many pure mathematicians are committed to purism, the ideology that values purity above applications in mathematics, and some historical reasons for this are discussed. MacIntyre’s virtue ethics accommodates both the good mathematician and the ethics of the social practice of mathematics. It demonstrates that purism is compatible with acknowledging the social responsibility of mathematics. Four aspects of this responsibility are mentioned, two concerning the impact of mathematics via education, and two concerning explicit and implicit applications of mathematics. The last of these opens up the performativity of mathematical and measurement applications in society, which change the very processes they are supposed to measure. Although these applications are not explored in detail, they illustrate the importance of considering the ethics and social responsibility of mathematics in society. MacIntyre’s virtue theory opens a broad approach to the controversial topic of the ethics of mathematics encompassing purism, and absolutist and social constructivist philosophies of mathematics, but still enabling ethical critiques of the impact of mathematics on society.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,349

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Towards a Philosophy of Applied Mathematics.Christopher Pincock - 2009 - In Otávio Bueno & Øystein Linnebo (eds.), New Waves in Philosophy of Mathematics. Palgrave-Macmillan.
Philosophy of mathematics education.Andrew Davis - 1992 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 26 (1):121–126.
Social Constructivism as a Philosophy of Mathematics.Paul Ernest - 1997 - Albany, NY, USA: State University of New York Press.
Values and Mathematics: Overt and Covert.Paul Ernest - 2016 - Culture and Dialogue 4 (1):48-82.
An introduction to the philosophy of mathematics.Mark Colyvan - 2012 - Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
The Position of Mathematics in Intellectual History.Toratarō Shimomura - 2018 - In Masakatsu Fujita (ed.), The Philosophy of the Kyoto School. Singapore: Springer Singapore. pp. 163-181.
Values and the Social Responsibility of Mathematics.Paul Ernest - 2007 - Philosophy of Mathematics Education Journal 22.
A “professional issues and ethics in mathematics” course.James Franklin - 2005 - Australian Mathematical Society Gazette 32:98-100.
The NCTM Standards and the Philosophy of Mathematics.Charalampos Toumasis - 1997 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 16 (3):317-330.

Analytics

Added to PP
2020-11-05

Downloads
38 (#408,165)

6 months
12 (#203,353)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

References found in this work

After virtue: a study in moral theory.Alasdair C. MacIntyre - 1984 - Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press.
We have never been modern.Bruno Latour - 1993 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
The emperor’s new mind.Roger Penrose - 1989 - Oxford University Press.
The nature of mathematical knowledge.Philip Kitcher - 1983 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Platonism and anti-Platonism in mathematics.Mark Balaguer - 1998 - New York: Oxford University Press.

View all 36 references / Add more references