Computational reverse mathematics and foundational analysis

Abstract

Reverse mathematics studies which subsystems of second order arithmetic are equivalent to key theorems of ordinary, non-set-theoretic mathematics. The main philosophical application of reverse mathematics proposed thus far is foundational analysis, which explores the limits of different foundations for mathematics in a formally precise manner. This paper gives a detailed account of the motivations and methodology of foundational analysis, which have heretofore been largely left implicit in the practice. It then shows how this account can be fruitfully applied in the evaluation of major foundational approaches by a careful examination of two case studies: a partial realization of Hilbert’s program due to Simpson [1988], and predicativism in the extended form due to Feferman and Schütte. Shore [2010, 2013] proposes that equivalences in reverse mathematics be proved in the same way as inequivalences, namely by considering only omega-models of the systems in question. Shore refers to this approach as computational reverse mathematics. This paper shows that despite some attractive features, computational reverse mathematics is inappropriate for foundational analysis, for two major reasons. Firstly, the computable entailment relation employed in computational reverse mathematics does not preserve justification for the foundational programs above. Secondly, computable entailment is a Pi-1-1 complete relation, and hence employing it commits one to theoretical resources which outstrip those available within any foundational approach that is proof-theoretically weaker than Pi-1-1-CA0.

Links

PhilArchive

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

  • Only published works are available at libraries.

Similar books and articles

Reverse mathematics: the playground of logic.Richard A. Shore - 2010 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 16 (3):378-402.
The Dirac delta function in two settings of Reverse Mathematics.Sam Sanders & Keita Yokoyama - 2012 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 51 (1-2):99-121.
Reverse-engineering Reverse Mathematics.Sam Sanders - 2013 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 164 (5):528-541.
Minima of initial segments of infinite sequences of reals.Jeffry L. Hirst - 2004 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 50 (1):47-50.
Questioning Constructive Reverse Mathematics.I. Loeb - 2012 - Constructivist Foundations 7 (2):131-140.
Reverse Mathematics and Ordinal Multiplication.Jeffry L. Hirst - 1998 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 44 (4):459-464.
Towards a Philosophy of Applied Mathematics.Christopher Pincock - 2009 - In Otávio Bueno & Øystein Linnebo (eds.), New Waves in Philosophy of Mathematics. Palgrave-Macmillan.
Reverse formalism 16.Sam Sanders - 2020 - Synthese 197 (2):497-544.
Reverse Mathematics and Completeness Theorems for Intuitionistic Logic.Takeshi Yamazaki - 2001 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 42 (3):143-148.
Reverse mathematics of prime factorization of ordinals.Jeffry L. Hirst - 1999 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 38 (3):195-201.

Analytics

Added to PP
2018-07-10

Downloads
276 (#70,596)

6 months
57 (#74,349)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Benedict Eastaugh
University of Warwick

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Systems of predicative analysis.Solomon Feferman - 1964 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 29 (1):1-30.
Fragments of arithmetic.Wilfried Sieg - 1985 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 28 (1):33-71.
Ramsey's theorem and recursion theory.Carl G. Jockusch - 1972 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 37 (2):268-280.
Why a Little Bit Goes a Long Way: Logical Foundations of Scientifically Applicable Mathematics.Solomon Feferman - 1992 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1992:442 - 455.

View all 16 references / Add more references