Truth Without Reference: The Use of Fictional Names

Topoi 39 (2):389-399 (2020)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Singular terms without referents are called empty or vacuous terms. But not all of them are equally empty. In particular, not all proper names that fail to name an existing object fail in the same way: although they are all empty, they are not all equally vacuous. “Vulcan,” “Jacob Horn,” “Odysseus,” and “Sherlock Holmes,” for instance, are all empty. They have no referents. But they are not entirely vacuous or useless. Sometimes they are used in statements that are true or false. We are basically referentialists about proper names. The ordinary semantic function of a proper name is to refer to an object, and to do it directly, that is, without semantically providing any identifying condition that the object should meet to be the referent. To put it differently, we agree that statements containing proper names express singular propositions, i.e., that their truth-conditions involve the referent of the proper name, if it exists, and not any identifying condition of it. Now, since empty names lack a referent, and therefore would not express such a singular proposition, how do we explain that many, if not all, statements containing them have a truth-value? Answering this question for the case of fictional names, in particular, is the aim of this paper.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,322

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Truths Containing Empty Names.Michael McKinsey - 2016 - In Piotr Stalmaszczyk & Luis Fernandez Moreno (eds.), Philosophical Approaches to Proper Names. Peter Lang. pp. 175-202.
Naming and Nonexistence.Neil Feit - 2009 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 47 (3):239-262.
How to Use Proper Names.Henri Lauener - 1994 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 49 (1):101-119.
Proper Names and their Fictional Uses.Heidi Tiedke - 2011 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 89 (4):707 - 726.
Description, Disagreement, and Fictional Names.Peter Alward - 2011 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 41 (3):423-448.
Actualisme et fiction.Jérôme Pelletier - 2000 - Dialogue 39 (1):77-.
Understanding proper names.Michael McKinsey - 2010 - Linguistics and Philosophy 33 (4):325-354.
How to Use Proper Names.Henri Lauener - 1994 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 49 (1):101-119.
Recovering What Is Said With Empty Names.Gualtiero Piccinini & Sam Scott - 2010 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 40 (2):239-273.
Empty Names and Pragmatic Millianism.Seyed N. Mousavian - 2014 - Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 3 (1):49-58.
The significance of names.Robin Jeshion - 2009 - Mind and Language 24 (4):370-403.

Analytics

Added to PP
2018-02-14

Downloads
147 (#124,107)

6 months
16 (#149,874)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author Profiles

John Perry
University of California, Riverside
Maria De Ponte Azkarate
University of the Basque Country
Kepa Korta
University of Basque Country

References found in this work

Naming and Necessity.S. Kripke - 1972 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 45 (4):665-666.
Naming and Necessity.Saul Kripke - 1980 - Critica 17 (49):69-71.
Reference and Existence: The John Locke Lectures.Saul A. Kripke - 2013 - New York: Oxford University Press.
The Causal Theory of Names.Gareth Evans - 1973 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 47 (1):187–208.
Reference and Reflexivity.John Perry - 2009 - Critica 41 (123):147-162.

View all 13 references / Add more references