Performability of Actions

Journal of Logic, Language and Information 30 (4):753-804 (2021)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Action theory may be regarded as a theoretical foundation of AI, because it provides in a logically coherent way the principles of performing actions by agents. But, more importantly, action theory offers a formal ontology mainly based on set-theoretic constructs. This ontology isolates various types of actions as structured entities: atomic, sequential, compound, ordered, situational actions etc., and it is a solid and non-removable foundation of any rational activity. The paper is mainly concerned with a bunch of issues centered around the notion of performability of actions. It seems that the problem of performability of actions, though of basic importance for purely practical applications, has not been investigated in the literature in a systematic way thus far. This work, being a companion to the book as reported, elaborates the theory of performability of actions based on relational models and formal constructs borrowed from formal lingusistics. The discussion of performability of actions is encapsulated in the form of a strict logical system. This system is semantically defined in terms of its intended models in which the role of actions of various types is accentuated. Since due to the nature of compound actions the system is not finitary, other semantic variants of are defined. The focus in on the system of performability of finite compound actions. An adequate axiom system for is defined. The strong completeness theorem is the central result. The role of the canonical model in the proof of the completeness theorem is highlighted. The relationship between performability of actions and dynamic logic is also discussed.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,386

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Negative actions.Benjamin Mossel - 2009 - Philosophia 37 (2):307-333.
Slip-Proof Actions.Santiago Amaya - 2016 - In Roman Altshuler & Michael J. Sigrist (eds.), Time and the Philosophy of Action. Routledge. pp. 21-36.
Is Raising One's Arm a Basic Action?Hugh McCann - 1972 - Journal of Philosophy 69 (9):235.
Actions as Events.Ming Xu - 2012 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 41 (4):765 - 809.
Actions and Events: A Study in Ontology and Ethics.Tracy Isaacs - 1992 - Dissertation, Massachusetts Institute of Technology
Being in the world.Joseph Raz - 2010 - Ratio 23 (4):433-452.
Agents and their actions.Maria Alvarez & John Hyman - 1998 - Philosophy 73 (2):219-245.
Composite Action.Sara Rachel Chant - 2004 - Dissertation, The University of Wisconsin - Madison
Comment: Every Action Is an Emotional Action.Bence Nanay - 2017 - Emotion Review 9 (4):350-352.
Action theory and the value of sport.Jon Pike - 2019 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 46 (1):14-29.

Analytics

Added to PP
2021-10-07

Downloads
9 (#1,224,450)

6 months
1 (#1,510,037)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Theory of Logical Calculi: Basic Theory of Consequence Operations.Ryszard Wójcicki - 1988 - Dordrecht, Boston and London: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Protoalgebraic Logics.Janusz Czelakowski - 2001 - Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Nonmonotonic causal theories.Joohyung Lee, Vladimir Lifschitz & Hudson Turner - 2004 - Artificial Intelligence 153 (1-2):49-104.
Protoalgebraic Logics.Janusz Czelakowski - 2003 - Studia Logica 74 (1):313-342.
The logic of deliberate action.Krister Segerberg - 1982 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 11 (2):233 - 254.

View all 10 references / Add more references