Collingwood, Bradley, and historical knowledge

History and Theory 45 (2):178–203 (2006)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

The central feature of the narrative structure of Collingwood’s The Idea of History is the pivotal role accorded to Bradley, evident in the table of contents and in the two discussions of him. Few readers have noticed that, confusingly, the book’s first discussion of Bradley is a revision of the Inaugural Lecture “The Historical Imagination,” which constitutes the book’s second discussion of Bradley . The differences between these two presentations of Bradley are significant. The 1935 account seeks to portray the Bradley of the Presuppositions of Critical History as a Copernican revolutionary in historical thought, even though the neo-Kantian transcendentalism promoted in the Lecture had been the core of Collingwood’s approach to philosophy of history from the mid-1920s, many years before he encountered Bradley’s essay. By 1935 this transcendentalism was in the process of self-destructing because of inner contradictions. By 1936, once Collingwood’s narrative and his criticisms of Bradley left the 1935 claims unsustainable, Collingwood shifted attention to Bradley’s later works, in an unsuccessful attempt to sustain the notion of his originality . Hitherto neglected Collingwood manuscripts held in the Bodleian prove that by 1940 Collingwood recognized this, so that the prominence Knox gave to Bradley in his editing of the IH is demonstrably not in accord with Collingwood’s views and plans for The Idea of History. Knox’s much-disputed claim that there was a radical shift to historicism in the later Collingwood is, however, confirmed, clear proof being adduced that in the later 1930s the attempt transcendentally to deduce universal and necessary presuppositions of historical knowledge is abandoned for a radically historicist account, paralleled by a demotion of “critical history” as the final form of “history proper” in favor of “scientific history.”

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,219

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Collingwood and Weber vs. Mink: History after the Cognitive Turn.Stephen Turner - 2011 - Journal of the Philosophy of History 5 (2):230-260.
The 'object' of historical knowledge.Patrick Gardiner - 1952 - Philosophy 27 (102):211-220.
Collingwood's Theory of Historical Knowledge.G. K. Grant - 1957 - Renaissance and Modern Studies 1:65-90.
From norms to uses and back again.Karim Dharamsi - 2008 - Journal of the Philosophy of History 2 (2):167-184.
Metaphysics, History and the Unpublished Manuscripts.John Luckman - 1991 - International Studies in Philosophy 23 (3):27-45.

Analytics

Added to PP
2009-01-28

Downloads
54 (#283,495)

6 months
4 (#698,851)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Citations of this work

Collingwood, Bradley, and Critical History.Robert F. DeVall - 2017 - Journal of the Philosophy of History 11 (3):378-390.
“All history is the history of thought”: competing British idealist historiographies.Colin Tyler - 2020 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 28 (3):573-593.

Add more citations

References found in this work

No references found.

Add more references