Religious Zeal, Political Faction and the Corruption of Morals: Adam Smith and the Limits of Enlightenment

Dissertation, The University of Chicago (2002)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

While Adam Smith develops a sophisticated account of the natural development of moral sentiments that denies the necessity of stringent religious or other moral indoctrination, he is aware of the limits of such sentiments in guaranteeing morality. Sympathy and the desire for the approval of others can, depending on the circumstances, lead either to conventional morality and social harmony or to the aggravation of political faction or religious zeal, depending on whose sympathy we seek. Even the love of virtue and the love of wisdom, when embodied in false religious or philosophical doctrines, are not immune to fanaticism. Our natural sociability, while more a more accurate understanding of human nature than the "selfish system of morals" of Hobbes, Locke, and Mandeville, turns out to be a mixed blessing. Nature or natural morality needs help. ;Similarly, while he develops a sophisticated account of the benefits of political and economic liberty, he is aware that such liberty requires substantial political prudence both to establish and maintain. Despite this understanding that nature needs human help, and his efforts to benefit mankind as a philosophic advisor to statesmen, he is also aware of the severe limits of philosophy, and particularly systematic political or economic philosophy. If it is systematic, it is simplistic and runs the danger of aggravating ideological fanaticism and generating harmful unintended consequences. If it avoids that danger, its moderation tends to guarantee its impotence. His system is thus an anti-system and relies on institutional changes that he hopes will indirectly promote a moderate politics largely free of religious and political fanaticism. ;Despite his reputation as a dogmatic systematizer, Smith is really a non-dogmatic skeptic. His attitude towards natural harmony and the human situation is neither Stoic resignation nor utopian hubris, neither the cynicism of Mandeville nor the romanticism of Rousseau. He thus displays a combination of superior prudence and skeptical humility. One may ask whether he does not also display more benevolence than more aggressive enlighteners, with their utopian imprudence and dogmatic skepticism.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,349

External links

  • This entry has no external links. Add one.
Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Adam Smith and the character of virtue.Ryan Patrick Hanley - 2009 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
La psychologie politique d’Adam Smith: Biais cognitifs et différences sociales dans la Théorie des sentiments moraux.Daniel Schulthess - 2009 - Studia Philosophica: Jahrbuch Der Schweizerischen Philosoph Ischen Gesellschaft, Annuaire de la Société Suisse de Philosphie 68:207-218.
Religion and community: Adam Smith on the virtues of liberty.Charles L. Griswold - 1997 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 35 (3):395-419.
Adam Smith’s Marketplace of Life.James R. Otteson - 2002 - Cambridge University Press.
The Theory of Moral Sentiments.Adam Smith - 1759 - Mineola, N.Y.: Dover Publications. Edited by Elizabeth Schmidt Radcliffe, Richard McCarty, Fritz Allhoff & Anand Vaidya.
Sentimentalism and the Is-Ought Problem.Noriaki Iwasa - 2011 - Croatian Journal of Philosophy 11 (3):323-352.

Analytics

Added to PP
2015-02-04

Downloads
0

6 months
0

Historical graph of downloads

Sorry, there are not enough data points to plot this chart.
How can I increase my downloads?

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

No references found.

Add more references