The Basis of Correctness in the Religious Studies Classroom

Journal of Philosophy of Education 50 (4):669-688 (2016)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

What is it that makes a student's answer correct or incorrect in Religious Studies? In practice, the standards of correctness in the Religious Studies classroom are generally applied with relative ease by teachers and students. Nevertheless, they are problematic. We shall argue that correctness does not come from either the students or the teacher believing that what has been said is true. This raises the question: what is correctness, if it does not come down to truth? We propose, and examine, three rival solutions, each of which, to an extent, rationalises a fairly natural response to the problem. The first, the elliptical approach, says that correct contributions have some tacit content: they are elliptical for true sentences about beliefs. The second, the imaginative approach, seeks to replace appeals to truth and belief with an appeal to imagination, treating Religious Studies as a ‘game of make-believe’ in which teachers and students imaginatively engage with certain worldviews. The third, the institutional approach, locates the root of correctness in the practices of the Religious Studies institution, which include making endorsements of some judgements and not others. We show that the first of our proposed approaches encounters a number of significant objections. We find the second of our proposed approaches to be better, but the third is the most attractive, providing a direct, intuitive and comprehensive route through the problem of correctness.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,202

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Belief, Correctness and normativity.Davide Fassio - 2011 - Logique Et Analyse 54 (216):471.
Doxastic Correctness.Ralph Wedgwood - 2013 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 87 (1):217-234.
What is a Logically Correct Argument?Michael Robert Gehman - 1990 - Dissertation, University of California, Los Angeles
Relative Correctness.Teresa Marques - 2014 - Philosophical Studies 167 (2):361-373.
Asking Questions of Nature.Donald Mark Bauder - 1991 - Dissertation, The University of Wisconsin - Madison
Political correctness: a critique.Peter Duignan - 1995 - Stanford, [Calif.]: Hoover Institution. Edited by Lewis H. Gann.
Paulo Freire and political correctness.Peter Roberts - 1997 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 29 (2):83–101.
Fitting belief.Conor McHugh - 2014 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 114 (2pt2):167-187.
The Competing Claims of the World's Religions: A Proposal.Robert Mark Fowler - 1996 - Dissertation, University of Colorado at Boulder
Why content must be a matter of truth conditions.Angus Ross - 1989 - Philosophical Quarterly 39 (156):257-275.
The Leisure of the Theory Class: Political Correctness or Professional Correctness?T. Luke - 1993 - Telos: Critical Theory of the Contemporary 1993 (97):97-104.

Analytics

Added to PP
2016-03-21

Downloads
39 (#388,687)

6 months
1 (#1,459,555)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author Profiles

Emily Caddick Bourne
University of Manchester
Craig Bourne
University of Hertfordshire

Citations of this work

Assessment, Truth and Religious Studies.John Tillson - 2019 - Studies in Philosophy and Education (2):195-210.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Mimesis as Make-Believe.Kendall L. Walton - 1996 - Synthese 109 (3):413-434.
Mathematics and Reality.Mary Leng - 2010 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Fiction and Fictionalism.R. M. Sainsbury - 2009 - New York: Routledge.
Mathematics and reality.Mary Leng - 2010 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 17 (2):267-268.

View all 7 references / Add more references