Intention-Based Semantics

In Ernest Lepore & Barry C. Smith (eds.), The Oxford Handbook to the Philosophy of Language. Oxford University Press. pp. 250--266 (2006)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

There is a sense in which it is trivial to say that one accepts intention- (or convention-) based semantics.[2] For if what is meant by this claim is simply that there is an important respect in which words and sentences have meaning (either at all or the particular meanings that they have in any given natural language) due to the fact that they are used, in the way they are, by intentional agents (i.e. speakers), then it seems no one should disagree. For imagine a possible world where there are physical things which share the shape and form of words of English or Japanese, or the acoustic properties of sentences of Finnish or Arapaho, yet where there are no intentional agents (or where any remaining intentional agents don’t use language). In such a world, it seems clear that these physical objects, which are only superficially language-like, will lack all meaning. Furthermore, it seems that questions of particular meaning are also settled by the conventions of intentional language users: it’s nothing more than convention which makes the concatenation of letters ‘a’^‘p’^‘p’^‘l’^‘e’ mean apple, rather than banana, in English.[3] So, understood as the minimal claim that intentional agents, who have a practice of using certain physical objects (written words, sounds, hand gestures, etc) to communicate certain thoughts, are a prerequisite for linguistic meaning, the idea that semantics is based on both intention and convention seems indisputable. I will label a theory which recognises this preconditional role for speaker intentions an A-style intention-based semantics and we will explore one such account in §1

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,386

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

A knowledge based semantics of messages.Rohit Parikh & Ramaswamy Ramanujam - 2003 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 12 (4):453-467.
Meaning, belief, and language acquisition.Mark Risjord - 1996 - Philosophical Psychology 9 (4):465-475.
John Searle.Joshua Rust - 2009 - Continuum.
Intensional verbs and their intentional objects.Friederike Moltmann - 2008 - Natural Language Semantics 16 (3):239-270.
Knowledge, Content and the Wellsprings of Objectivity.Ron Wilburn - 2003 - In Preyer Gerhard, Peter Georg & Ulkan Maria (eds.), Protosociology. Klewer Academic Publishers.
Meaning, expression, and thought.Wayne A. Davis - 2003 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
Pragmatics and Cognition: Intentions and Pattern Recognition in Context.Marco Mazzone - 2009 - International Review of Pragmatics 1 (2):321-347.

Analytics

Added to PP
2009-01-28

Downloads
189 (#101,772)

6 months
9 (#295,075)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Emma Borg
University of Reading

Citations of this work

Are explicatures cancellable?Alessandro Capone - 2009 - Intercultural Pragmatics 6 (1):55-83.
Trust, relevance, and arguments.Fabio Paglieri & Cristiano Castelfranchi - 2014 - Argument and Computation 5 (2-3):216-236.
politeness Towards an evaluative and embodied approach.Chaoqun Xie - 2008 - Pragmatics and Cognition 16 (1):151-175.
The Semantic Theory and the Availability Principle.Hsiu-Lin Ku - 2014 - NTU Philosophical Review 48:123-158.

Add more citations

References found in this work

No references found.

Add more references