Thomas Aquinas on the Basis of the Irascible-Concupiscible Division

Res Philosophica 97 (1):31-52 (2020)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Thomas Aquinas divides the sensory appetite into two powers: the irascible and the concupiscible. The irascible power moves creatures toward arduous goods and away from arduous evils, while the concupiscible power moves creatures toward pleasant goods and away from non-arduous evils. Despite the importance of this distinction, it remains unclear what counts as an arduous good or evil, and why arduousness is the defining feature of the division. The aim of this paper is twofold. First, I argue that an arduous object is one that is difficult and important for the creature. Second, given this proper understanding of arduousness, I highlight the shortcomings of the standard interpretation of Aquinas’s argument for the irascible-concupiscible distinction and suggest an alternative. I argue that Aquinas grounds the distinction in the distinction between useful and pleasant goods. I explain how these distinct goods allow arduousness to be the defining feature of the irascible-concupiscible division.

Other Versions

No versions found

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 100,061

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Analytics

Added to PP
n/a

Downloads
96 (#192,171)

6 months
26 (#119,245)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Christopher A. Bobier
Central Michigan University

References found in this work

Action, Emotion and Will.Anthony Kenny - 1963 - Philosophy 39 (149):277-278.
The value of hope.Luc Bovens - 1999 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 59 (3):667-681.
On the Soul. Aristotle - 1984 - In Jonathan Barnes (ed.), The Complete Works: The Rev. Oxford Translation. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press. pp. 641-692.
Hope and its Place in Mind.Phillip Pettit - 2004 - Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science (1):152--165.

View all 10 references / Add more references