John Austin and Constructing Theories of Law

Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 24 (2):431-440 (2011)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

One of the standard criticisms of John Austin’s work is that his portrayal of law, as essentially the command of a sovereign to its subjects, does not fit well with the way law is practiced or perceived by lawyers, judges, and citizens; and since the theory “fails to fit the facts,” Austin’s theory must be rejected in favor of later theories that have better fit. Many influential modern approaches to the nature of law, including Joseph Raz’s exclusive legal positivism and Ronald Dworkin’s interpretivism, while they criticize the lack of fit of theories like Austin’s, themselves unapologetically offer characterizations of legal practice that deviate in significant ways from the way most people practice or perceive law. Thus, it appears that many contemporary legal theorists wish to have it both ways: they use the deviations from conventional understandings as grounds for dismissing some theories by other scholars, but forgive or overlook comparable deviations in their own theories. This article explores what general principles can be learned, or developed, regarding when or to what extent deviation from the way law is practiced and perceived can be justified in a theory of the nature of law by other theoretical gains. Additionally, the article considers whether, in light of the proper approach to fit and mistake in theory-construction, Austin’s theory of law might be a more viable alternative than is conventionally assumed

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,164

External links

  • This entry has no external links. Add one.
Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Austin, Kelsen, and the Model of Sovereignty.Lars Vinx - 2011 - Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 24 (2):473-490.
Austin and the Electors.Pavlos Eleftheriadis - 2011 - Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 24 (2):441-453.
Ten Conditions on a Theory of Speech Acts.Barry Smith - 1984 - Theoretical Linguistics 11 (3):309-330.
Philosophy of law.Brian Bix (ed.) - 2006 - Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon ; New York, NY: Routledge.
A Dictionary of Legal Theory.Brian Bix - 2004 - New York: Oxford University Press.
John Langshaw Austin.Federica Berdini, and & Claudia Bianchi - 2013 - Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Literalism and imagination: Wittgenstein's deconstruction of traditional philosophy.David Pears - 2002 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 10 (1):3 – 16.
The province of jurisprudence determined and The uses of the study of jurisprudence.John Austin - 1954 - London,: Weidenfeld & Nicolson. Edited by John Austin.
Austin, Hobbes, and Dicey.David Dyzenhaus - 2011 - Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 24 (2):411-440.
What can Austin tell us about truth?Jeffrey Hershfield - 2010 - Philosophical Investigations 33 (3):220-228.

Analytics

Added to PP
2015-01-22

Downloads
2 (#1,750,398)

6 months
1 (#1,444,594)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Brian Bix
University of Minnesota

Citations of this work

Popular sovereignty facing the deep state. The rule of recognition and the powers of the people.Ludvig Beckman - 2021 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 24 (7):954-976.

Add more citations

References found in this work

No references found.

Add more references