The works of art from the philosophically innocent point of view

Hungarian Philosophical Review 57 (4):7-17 (2012)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

the Mona Lisa, the Mondscheinsonate, the Chanson d’automne are works of art, the salt shaker on your table, the car in your garage, or the pijamas on your bed are not. the basic question of the metaphysics of works of art is this: what makes a thing a work of art? that is: what sort of property do works of art have in virtue of which they are works of art? or more simply: what sort of property being a work of art is? In this paper we argue that things are works of art in virtue of what they are like, their intrinsic features, that is, in virtue of the fact that they have the perceptual (auditory, visual, etc.) properties they have. In other words: being a work of art supervenes on perceptual-intrinsic features. Currently, this metaphysical view is extremely unpopular within the philosophy of art. It is unpopular because there allegedly exists a knock-down objection to it, the well-known argument from indiscernible counterparts. our thesis implies, among other things, that every perceptual duplicate of a work of art is also a work of art. according to the argument from indiscernible counterparts, however, there could be (or even: there are) indiscernible counterparts such that one of them is a work of art while the other is not. hence things cannot be works of art solely in virtue of what they are like. Our paper divides into three parts. In the first part we state our views. In the second part we defend it against various versions of the argument from indiscernible counterparts. (In doing so our position will become more plausible, we hope). In the final part we provide some meta-reflections on the matter.

Links

PhilArchive

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Copyright and Its Categories of Original Works.Justine Pila - 2010 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 30 (2):229-254.
Is there a problem of indiscernible counterparts?John Andrew Fisher - 1995 - Journal of Philosophy 92 (9):467-484.
On judging the moral value of narrative artworks.James Harold - 2006 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 64 (2):259–270.
Work and object.Peter Lamarque - 2002 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 102 (2):141–162.
A functional view of artistic evaluation.Jonathan Gilmore - 2011 - Philosophical Studies 155 (2):289-305.
Platonism in Music.Peter Kivy - 1983 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 19 (1):109-129.
A religious point of view.Elizabeth Wolgast - 2004 - Philosophical Investigations 27 (2):129–147.
Necessity in singular causation.M. J. García-Encinas - 2002 - Philosophia 29 (1-4):149-172.

Analytics

Added to PP
2014-01-29

Downloads
973 (#13,374)

6 months
116 (#30,120)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

János Tőzsér
Research Centre for The Humanities, Budapest, Hungary

Citations of this work

“This is not Art” — Should we go Revisionist about Works of Art?Tibor Bárány - 2013 - Proceedings of the European Society for Aesthetics 5:86-99.

Add more citations

References found in this work

On the Plurality of Worlds.David K. Lewis - 1986 - Malden, Mass.: Wiley-Blackwell.
The Republic.Paul Plato & Shorey - 2000 - ePenguin. Edited by Cynthia Johnson, Holly Davidson Lewis & Benjamin Jowett.
The limits of self-awareness.Michael G. F. Martin - 2004 - Philosophical Studies 120 (1-3):37-89.
The principles of art.R. G. Collingwood - 1938 - New York,: Oxford University Press.
On the Plurality of Worlds.James E. Tomberlin - 1989 - Noûs 23 (1):117-125.

View all 16 references / Add more references