Skill‐selection and socioeconomic status: An analysis of migration and domestic justice

Journal of Social Philosophy 53 (4):595-613 (2022)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

In this paper I present two reasons why generalized skill-selection--a policy whereby skill, education, and economic independence are indefinitely prioritized in immigration decisions--is pro tanto unjust. First, such policies feed into existing biases, exacerbating status harms for low-SES citizens. The claim that we prefer the skilled to the unskilled, the educated to the uneducated, and the financially secure to the insecure is also heard by citizens. And there is considerable overlap between this message and the stereotypes and biases that set their social status. Skill-selection can reinforce these biases, offering state support for the claim that they are less desirable as members of the society. Second, the need for skilled immigrants ordinarily depends upon and reinforces failures of fair equality of opportunity (FEO). According to the dependency thesis, the need for skilled migrants stems from a failure to ensure domestic FEO. Many low-SES residents would desire to work, for example, as doctors or nurses. However, unequal education, as well as poverty and debt, have made such opportunities largely inaccessible. According to the reinforcement thesis, skill-selection disincentivizes the pursuit of FEO. A state that can meet domestic labor needs through less costly immigration policies will be disinclined to pursue programs designed to equalize opportunities for low-SES residents. Generalized skill-selection in high-income countries like the US is, therefore, pro tanto unjust. However, this is not an argument for excluding the skilled. Skilled immigrants can be admitted through other policies—open borders, family-reunification, or a lottery—without the state signaling that the skilled are more desirable or perpetuating failures of FEO. And states can, responding to local emergencies, temporarily select for particular professions without contributing to these injustices. These concerns only arise when skill is generally and indefinitely prioritized.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,219

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Justice in migration.Christine Straehle - 2018 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 48 (2):245-265.
Health disparities and autonomy.Andrew Courtwright - 2008 - Bioethics 22 (8):431-439.
The Moral Implications of the Global Basic Structure as a Subject of Justice.Fausto Corvino - 2019 - Glocialism. Journal of culture, politics and innovation 2019 (2):1-36.
“Care drain”. Explaining bias in theorizing women’s migration.Speranta Dumitru - 2016 - Romanian Journal of Society and Politics 11 (2):7-24.
Environmental Justice. Perhac - 1999 - Environmental Ethics 21 (1):81-92.

Analytics

Added to PP
2022-07-16

Downloads
44 (#344,726)

6 months
17 (#132,430)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Michael Ball-Blakely
University of Texas at El Paso

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Justice as fairness: a restatement.John Rawls (ed.) - 2001 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
The Ethics of Immigration.Joseph Carens - 2013 - New York: Oxford University Press.

View all 18 references / Add more references