History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences

ISSNs: 0391-9714, 1742-6316

16 found

View year:

  1.  9
    “Naked life”: the vital meaning of nutrition in Claude Bernard’s physiology.Cécilia Bognon-Küss - 2024 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 46 (2):1-29.
    The aim of this paper is to elucidate the vital meaning and strategic role that nutrition holds in Claude Bernard’s “biological philosophy”, in the sense Auguste Comte gave to this expression, _i.e._ the theoretical part of biology. I propose that Bernard’s nutritive perspective on life should be thought of as an “interfield” object, following Holmes’ category. Not only does nutrition bridge disciplines like physiology and organic chemistry, as well as levels of inquiry ranging from special physiology to the organism’s total (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  10
    The discovery of archaea: from observed anomaly to consequential restructuring of the phylogenetic tree.Michael Fry - 2024 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 46 (2):1-38.
    Observational and experimental discoveries of new factual entities such as objects, systems, or processes, are major contributors to some advances in the life sciences. Yet, whereas discovery of theories was extensively deliberated by philosophers of science, very little philosophical attention was paid to the discovery of factual entities. This paper examines historical and philosophical aspects of the experimental discovery by Carl Woese of archaea, prokaryotes that comprise one of the three principal domains of the phylogenetic tree. Borrowing Kuhn’s terminology, this (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  14
    Race and indigeneity in human microbiome science: microbiomisation and the historiality of otherness.Andrea Núñez Casal - 2024 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 46 (2):1-27.
    This article reformulates Stephan Helmreich´s the ¨microbiomisation of race¨ as the historiality of otherness in the foundations of human microbiome science. Through the lens of my ethnographic fieldwork of a transnational community of microbiome scientists that conducted a landmark human microbiome research on indigenous microbes and its affiliated and first personalised microbiome initiative, the American Gut Project, I follow and trace the key actors, experimental systems and onto-epistemic claims in the emergence of human microbiome science a decade ago. In doing (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  17
    After the trans brain: a critique of the neurobiological accounts of embodied trans* identities.Maite Arraiza Zabalegui - 2024 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 46 (1):1-24.
    This paper critically analyses three main neurobiological hypotheses on trans* identities: the neurobiological theory about the origin of gender dysphoria, the neurodevelopmental cortical hypothesis, and the alternative hypothesis of self-referential thinking and body perception. In this study I focus then the attention on three elements: the issue of (de)pathologisation, the idea of the trans brain, and the aetiology of trans* identities. While the neurobiological theory about the origin of gender dysphoria and the neurodevelopmental cortical hypothesis claim the existence of the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  9
    Embodied cognition and the imaging of bio-pathologies: the question of experiential primacy in detecting diagnostic phenomena.Mindaugas Briedis - 2024 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 46 (1):1-29.
    This article investigates the origins of the experiences involved in the diagnostics (detection and normative evaluation) of biological entities in image-based medical praxis. Our specific research aim presupposes a vast discussion regarding the origins of knowledge in general, but is narrowed down to the alternatives of anthropomorphism and biomorphism. Accordingly, in the subsequent chapters we will make an attempt to investigate and illustrate what holds the diagnostic experiential situation together—biological regularities, manifestation via movement, conscious synthesis, causal categories, or something else. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  7
    How is who: evidence as clues for action in participatory sustainability science and public health research.Guido Caniglia & Federica Russo - 2024 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 46 (1):1-26.
    Participatory and collaborative approaches in sustainability science and public health research contribute to co-producing evidence that can support interventions by involving diverse societal actors that range from individual citizens to entire communities. However, existing philosophical accounts of evidence are not adequate to deal with the kind of evidence generated and used in such approaches. In this paper, we present an account of evidence as clues for action through participatory and collaborative research inspired by philosopher Susan Haack’s theory of evidence. Differently (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  2
    When remediating one artifact results in another: control, confounders, and correction.David Colaço - 2024 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 46 (1):1-18.
    Scientists aim to remediate artifacts in their experimental datasets. However, the remediation of one artifact can result in another. Why might this happen, and what does this consequence tell us about how we should account for artifacts and their control? In this paper, I explore a case in functional neuroimaging where remediation appears to have caused this problem. I argue that remediation amounts to a change to an experimental arrangement. These changes need not be surgical, and the arrangement need not (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  14
    On the nature of evolutionary explanations: a critical appraisal of Walter Bock’s approach with a new revised proposal.Marcelo Domingos de Santis - 2024 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 46 (1):1-24.
    Walter Bock was committed to developing a framework for evolutionary biology. Bock repeatedly discussed how evolutionary explanations should be considered within the realm of Hempel’s deductive-nomological model of scientific explanations. Explanation in evolution would then consist of functional and evolutionary explanations, and within the latter, an explanation can be of nomological-deductive and historical narrative explanations. Thus, a complete evolutionary explanation should include, first, a deductive functional analysis, and then proceed through nomological and historical evolutionary explanations. However, I will argue that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  6
    Diversification or sensory unification? Controversies around the senses in fin de siècle culture.Sonsoles Hernandez Barbosa - 2024 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 46 (1):1-17.
    This article analyses the evolutionist discourses on the senses that emerged in the late 19th century, when theories on the evolution of species were in full sway. Drawing on newspapers, essays and medical literature, this article aims to set face to face the two currents of thought that I have identified regarding sensory evolution: the one that stressed the value of the progressive specialisation of the senses as evidence for human evolution mainly supported by Max Nordau, and the one which (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  4
    How should we distinguish between selectable and circumstantial traits?Ciprian Jeler - 2024 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 46 (1):1-22.
    There is surprisingly little philosophical work on conceptually spelling out the difference between the traits on which natural selection may be said to act (e.g. “having a high running speed”) and mere circumstantial traits (e.g. “happening to be in the path of a forest fire”). I label this issue the “selectable traits problem” and, in this paper, I propose a solution for it. I first show that, contrary to our first intuition, simply equating selectable traits with heritable ones is not (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  10
    Reappraising Claude Bernard’s legacy: an introduction.Laurent Loison - 2024 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 46 (1):1-10.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  6
    Forgetting how we ate: personalised nutrition and the strategic uses of history.Christopher Mayes & Maurizio Meloni - 2024 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 46 (1):1-28.
    Personalised nutrition (PN) has emerged over the past twenty years as a promising area of research in the postgenomic era and has been popularized as the new big thing out of molecular biology. Advocates of PN claim that previous approaches to nutrition sought general and universal guidance that applied to all people. In contrast, they contend that PN operates with the principle that “one size does not fit all” when it comes to dietary guidance. While the molecular mechanisms studied within (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  9
    From the harmony to the tension: Helmuth Plessner and Kurt Goldstein’s readings of Jakob von Uexküll.Matteo Pagan & Marco Dal Pozzolo - 2024 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 46 (1):1-23.
    This paper investigates the reception and discussion of Jakob von Uexküll’s biological theory by two German thinkers of his time, Helmuth Plessner and Kurt Goldstein. It demonstrates how their bio-philosophical perspectives are on the one hand indebted to Uexküll’s theory and, on the other, critical of its tendency to excessively harmonize the relationship between living beings and their environment. This original critical reading of the _Umweltlehre_ is rooted in ambiguities within Uexküll’s own thought - between a dynamic conception of the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  2
    A work in progress: William Bateson’s vibratory theory of repetition of parts.Alan R. Rushton - 2024 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 46 (1):1-22.
    In 1891 Cambridge biologist William Bateson (1861–1926) announced his idea that the symmetrical segmentation in living organisms resulted from energy peaks of some vibratory force acting on tissues during morphogenesis. He also demonstrated topographically how folding a radially symmetric organism could produce another with bilateral symmetry. Bateson attended many lectures at the Cambridge Philosophical Society and viewed mechanical models prepared by eminent physicists that illustrated how vibrations affected materials. In his subsequent research, Bateson utilized analogies and metaphors based upon his (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  7
    Jacob Stegenga, Care & Cure. An introduction to philosophy of medicine, Chicago: the University of Chicago Press, 2018, 288 pp. [REVIEW]Isabella Sarto-Jackson - 2024 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 46 (1):1-5.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  7
    Scrutinizing microbiome determinism: why deterministic hypotheses about the microbiome are conceptually ungrounded.Javier Suárez - 2024 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 46 (1):1-26.
    This paper addresses the topic of determinism in contemporary microbiome research. I distinguish two types of deterministic claims about the microbiome, and I show evidence that both types of claims are present in the contemporary literature. First, the idea that the host genetics determines the composition of the microbiome which I call “host-microbiome determinism”. Second, the idea that the genetics of the holobiont (the individual unit composed by a host plus its microbiome) determines the expression of certain phenotypic traits, which (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
 Previous issues
  
Next issues