Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Trains of Thought Long Associated with Action.Trip Glazer - 2024 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 41 (1):1-22.
    It is sometimes said that Charles Darwin has a theory of emotional expression, but not a theory of emotion. This paper argues that Darwin does have a theory of emotion. Inspired by David Hartley and Erasmus Darwin, Charles Darwin claims that an emotion is a train of feelings, thoughts, and actions, linked by associations. Whereas Hartley and Erasmus insist that these associations are learned, Charles proposes that some of these associations are inherited. He develops this theory in his private notebooks (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the hierarchy of “reflexes”.Uwe Windhorst - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):625-626.
  • Beyond anatomical specificity.M. T. Turvey - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):624-625.
  • The education of behaviorism and the nature of learning.William Timberlake - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (4):638-639.
  • “The Fust Official Psychologist in the Wurrld”: Aspects of the Professionalization of Psychology in Early Twentieth Century Britain.Gillian Sutherland & Stephen Sharp - 1980 - History of Science 18 (3):181-208.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What every speaker cognizes.Stephen P. Stich - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):39-40.
  • Controlled versus automatic processing.Robert J. Sternberg - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):32-33.
  • Representation and psychological reality.Elliott Sober - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):38-39.
    In this brief space I want to describe how Chomsky's analysis of "psychological reality" departs from what I think is a fairly standard construal of the idea. This familiar formulation arises from distinguishing between someone's following a rule and someone's acting in conformity with a rule. The former idea, but not the latter, involves the idea that the person has some mental representation of the rule that plays a certain causal role in determining behavior. Although there may be many grammatical (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Do we have one brain or two? Babylon revisited?Aaron Smith - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):647-648.
  • Mencius's vertical faculties and moral nativism.Bongrae Seok - 2008 - Asian Philosophy 18 (1):51 – 68.
    This paper compares and contrasts Mencius's moral philosophy with recent development in cognitive science regarding mental capacity to understand moral rules and principles. Several cognitive scientists argue that the human mind has innate cognitive and emotive foundations of morality. In this paper, Mencius's moral theory is interpreted from the perspective of faculty psychology and cognitive modularity, a theoretical hypothesis in cognitive science in which the mind is understood as a system of specialized mental components. Specifically, Mencius's Four Beginnings (the basic (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Lexicon as module.Mark S. Seidenberg - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):31-32.
  • Rules and causation.John R. Searle - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):37-38.
  • Organic insight into mental organs.Barry Schwartz - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):30-31.
  • Encapsulation and expectation.Roger Schank & Larry Hunter - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):29-30.
  • Controlling the temporal structure of limb movements.Richard A. Schmidt - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):623-624.
  • An artificial intelligence perspective on Chomsky's view of language.Roger C. Schank - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):35-37.
  • A rapprochement of biology, psychology, and philosophy.Sandra Scarr - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):29-29.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Chomsky's evidence against Chomsky's theory.Geoffrey Sampson - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):34-35.
  • The modularity and maturation of cognitive capacities.David M. Rosenthal - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):32-34.
  • Gallistel's metatheory of action.H. L. Roitblat - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (4):637-638.
  • Implications of aiming.T. D. M. Roberts - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):622-623.
  • Faculties, modules, and computers.Daniel N. Robinson - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):28-29.
  • Multiple realization and methodological pluralism.Robert C. Richardson - 2009 - Synthese 167 (3):473-492.
    Multiple realization was once taken to be a challenge to reductionist visions, especially within cognitive science, and a foundation of the “antireductionist consensus.” More recently, multiple realization has come to be challenged on naturalistic grounds, as well as on more “metaphysical” grounds. Within cognitive science, one focal issue concerns the role of neural plasticity for addressing these issues. If reorganization maintains the same cognitive functions, that supports claims for multiple realization. I take up the reorganization involved in language dysfunctions to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Quinity, isotropy, and Wagnerian rapture.Georges Rey - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):27-28.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Behavior ignored.Peter C. Reynolds - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (4):637-637.
  • The trapped infinity: Cartesian volition as conceptual nightmare.Edward S. Reed - 1990 - Philosophical Psychology 3 (1):101-121.
    Abstract Descartes's theory of volition as expressed in his Passions of the Soul is analyzed and outlined. The focus is not on Descartes's proposed answers to questions about the nature and processes of volition, but on his way of formulating questions about the nature of volition. It is argued that the assumptions underlying Descartes's questions have become ?intellectual strait?jackets? for all who are interested in volition: neuroscientists, philosophers and psychologists. It is shown that Descartes's basic assumption?that volition causes change in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Motor variability but functional specificity: Demise of the concept of motor commands.Edward S. Reed - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):620-622.
  • Can mental representations cause behavior?Edward S. Reed - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (4):635-636.
  • Language, brain function, and human origins in the Victorian debates on evolution.Gregory Radick - 2000 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 31 (1):55-75.
  • Cross purposes.Howard Rachlln - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):30-31.
  • From phrenology to the laboratory.Tom Quick - 2014 - History of the Human Sciences 27 (5):54-73.
    The claim that mind is an epiphenomenon of the nervous system became academically respectable during the 19thcentury. The same period saw the establishment of an ideal of science as institutionalized endeavour conducted in laboratories. This article identifies three ways in which the ‘physiological psychology’ movement in Britain contributed to the latter process: first, via an appeal to the authority of difficult-to-access sites in the analysis of nerves; second, through the constitution of a discourse internal to it that privileged epistemology over (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Experiencing two selves: The history of a mistake.Roland Puccetti - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):646-647.
  • Giving behavior to psychology.Robert R. Provine - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (4):635-635.
  • Frogs solve Bernstein's problem.Lloyd D. Partridge - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):619-620.
  • Can voluntary movement be understood on the basis of reflex organization?David J. Ostry & Frances E. Wilkinson - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):618-619.
  • Continuity of thought on duality of brain and mind?Jane M. Oppenheimer - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):645-646.
  • Behavioral flexibility and the organization of action.David S. Olton - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (4):634-635.
  • Reciprocal reflex action and adaptive gain control in the context of the equilibrium-point hypothesis.T. Richard Nichols - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):617-618.
  • A basis for action.Allen Newell - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (4):633-634.
  • Do the α and λ models adequately describe reflex behavior in man?Peter D. Neilson - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):616-617.
  • Hierarchical structures in the organization of motor behaviors.Lewis M. Nashner - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (4):633-633.
  • What textbooks between 1887 and 1911 said about hemisphere differences.David J. Murray - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):644-645.
  • Motor equivalence and goal descriptors.Kevin G. Munhall - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):615-616.
  • Too little and latent.John Morton - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):26-27.
  • There are many modular theories of mind.Adam Morton - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):29-29.
  • Language: levels of characterisation.John Morton - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):29-30.
  • Chomsky's radical break with modern traditions.Julius M. Moravcsik - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):28-29.
  • Lateralization and sex.Ursula Mittwoch - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):644-644.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Two hemispheres do not make a dichotomy.A. David Milner - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):643-644.
  • A small fly in some beneficial ointment.P. M. Milner - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (4):632-633.