Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Action as a form of temporal unity: on Anscombe’s Intention.Douglas Lavin - 2015 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 45 (5):609-629.
    The aim of this paper is to display an alternative to the familiar decompositional approach in action theory, one that resists the demand for an explanation of action in non-agential terms, while not simply treating the notion of intentional agency as an unexplained primitive. On this Anscombean alternative, action is not a worldly event with certain psychological causes, but a distinctive form of material process, one that is not simply caused by an exercise of reason but is itself a productive (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Irrationality. [REVIEW]Béla Szabados - 1990 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 20 (3):403-415.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Reflections on surfaces.Avrum Stroll - 1992 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 22 (2):191-210.
    Can there be a first-order, philosophical or psychological theory that explains all the facts of surface perception? By ‘first-order’ I mean a theory about the constituents of what J.J. Gibson called ‘the ecological environment’; and by ‘surface perception,’ I mean the perception of the surfaces of any of those ecological constituents that have surfaces. The question about surfaces is important for two reasons. First, as we shall see, they are complex features and, as such, provide a difficult test case for (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wittgenstein, Davidson, and the Myth of Incommensurability.Stan Stein - 1993 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 23 (sup1):181-221.
    (1993). Wittgenstein, Davidson, and the Myth of Incommensurability. Canadian Journal of Philosophy: Vol. 23, Supplementary Volume 19: New Essays on Metaphilosophy, pp. 181-221.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Belief, normativity and the constitution of agency.Emer O'Hagan - 2005 - Philosophical Explorations 8 (1):39-52.
    In this paper I advance a constitutive argument for the authority of rational norms. Because accountability to reasons is constitutive of rational agency and rational norms are implicit in reasons for action and belief, the justification of rational norms is of a piece with the practice of reasoning. Peter Railton has objected that the constitutive view fails to defend the categorical authority of reason over agents. I respond to his objections, arguing that they presuppose a foundationalist conception of justification that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Skepticism and Critique in Arendt and Cavell.Andrew Norris - 2018 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 44 (1):81-99.
    In this article I compare and contrast Hannah Arendt’s and Stanley Cavell’s understandings of critique, focusing in each case upon the role played in it by skepticism. Both writers are decisively influenced by the later Heidegger’s thought that thinking as such is, first, the necessary turn to a practice adequate to our situation and, second, something that we shun. They also share the desire to take up this Heideggerian thought in Kantian terms: what is at stake is critical thinking. It (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • History Lessons: Eagleton and the Problem of the Space of Commentary.A. W. McHoul - 1984 - Theory, Culture and Society 2 (2):105-122.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Basic Sentences and Objectivity: A Private Language Argument.Nollaig MacKenzie - 1973 - Dialogue 12 (2):217-232.
    Thus consciousness belief and belief are one and the same being, the characteristic of which is absolute immanence. But as soon as we wish to grasp this being, it slips between our fingers, and we find ourselves faced with a pattern of duality, with a game of reflections. For consciousness is a reflection, but qua reflection it is exactly the one reflecting, and if we attempt to grasp it as reflecting, it vanishes and we fall back on the reflection.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • How to justify ‘militant democracy’.Miodrag Jovanović - 2016 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 42 (8):745-762.
    Decisions in democracy are binding not in virtue of being true or good, but on account of being an outcome of the majority voting procedure. For some, this is a proof of an intricate connection between democracy and moral relativism. The ‘militant democracy’ model, on the other hand, is premised on the idea that certain political actors and choices have to be banned for being fatally bad for democracy. This gives rise to the claim that protected democratic fundamental values of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Wisdom’s Philosophy of Religion: Part II: Metaphysical and Religious Transcendence.Ilham Dilman - 1975 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 5 (December):497-521.
    Wisdom holds that the reference in many religious beliefs to what lies beyond the world and "transcends" the senses is misleading. religious beliefs speak and can only speak about the world we know by means of the senses. to embrace much of what christians believe means for a person to change in himself and come into contact with something "within" him. i argue, first, that there is a sense of transcendence which is immune from wisdom's criticism and, secondly, that while (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Causal Generalisations in Policy-oriented Economic Research: An Inferentialist Analysis.François Claveau & Luis Mireles-Flores - 2016 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 30 (4):383-398.
    The most common way of analysing the meaning of causal generalisations relies on referentialist semantics. In this article, we instead develop an analysis based on inferentialist semantics. According to this approach, the meaning of a causal generalisation is constituted by the web of inferential connections in which the generalisation participates. We distinguish and discuss five classes of inferential connections that constitute the meaning of causal generalisations produced in policy-oriented economic research. The usefulness of our account is illustrated with the analysis (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Beasts, Beliefs, Intentions, Norms.David Checkland - 2009 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 39 (S1):299-335.
    “Terms that have histories cannot be defined.” – Nietzsche“[T]he reality to which we were attending seemed to resist our thinking it.” – Cora Diamond[1] Much has been learned in recent decades about the behaviour and abilities of many species of non-human animals. Increasingly many who reflect on the abilities of languageless animals are uncomfortable with a once prevalent dichotomy of either assigning these abilities to the realm of mere mechanism or granting such creatures full rationality and more or less the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is beauty an archaic spirit in education?Howard Cannatella - 2006 - Journal of Aesthetic Education 40 (1):94-103.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Is Beauty an Archaic Spirit in Education?Howard Cannatella (bio)O! Father and mother, if buds are nip'd and blossoms blown away, and if the tender plants are strip'd of their joy in the spring day, by sorrow and care's dismay, how shall the summer arise in joy, or the summer fruit appear?William Blake, "The School Boy"1This article discusses the unfashionable and taboo idea that beauty matters. A sign of the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Emotion and Thought in Hume's Treatise.John Bricke - 1975 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 5 (sup1):53-71.
    In this paper I examine Hume's theory of the emotions, as presented in his *Treatise of Human Nature*, paying particular attention to what he has to say about the relationships between emotion and thought. I begin by presenting, in some detail, Hume's views about the nature of the emotions, their causes, and their objects. I then consider the bearing of the private language argument on Hume's theory, and try to show that it is not sufficient to reveal the weaknesses in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Kant's transcendental idealism and contemporary anti‐realism.Lucy Allais - 2003 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 11 (4):369 – 392.
    This paper compares Kant's transcendental idealism with three main groups of contemporary anti-realism, associated with Wittgenstein, Putnam, and Dummett, respectively. The kind of anti-realism associated with Wittgenstein has it that there is no deep sense in which our concepts are answerable to reality. Associated with Putnam is the rejection of four main ideas: theory-independent reality, the idea of a uniquely true theory, a correspondence theory of truth, and bivalence. While there are superficial similarities between both views and Kant's, I find (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • The Significance of Learning in Wittgenstein’s Later Philosophy.Meredith Williams - 1994 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 24 (2):173-203.