Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Minds beyond brains and algorithms.Jan M. Zytkow - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):691-692.
  • Computability, consciousness, and algorithms.Robert Wilensky - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):690-691.
  • Penrose's grand unified mystery.David Waltz & James Pustejovsky - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):688-690.
  • Between Turing and quantum mechanics there is body to be found.Francisco J. Varela - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):687-688.
  • Exactly which emperor is Penrose talking about?John K. Tsotsos - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):686-687.
  • The thinker dreams of being an emperor.M. M. Taylor - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):685-686.
  • And then a miracle happens….Keith E. Stanovich - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):684-685.
  • The pretender's new clothes.Tim Smithers - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):683-684.
  • The tripartite model of representation.Peter Slezak - 2002 - Philosophical Psychology 15 (3):239-270.
    Robert Cummins [(1996) Representations, targets and attitudes, Cambridge, MA: Bradford/MIT, p. 1] has characterized the vexed problem of mental representation as "the topic in the philosophy of mind for some time now." This remark is something of an understatement. The same topic was central to the famous controversy between Nicolas Malebranche and Antoine Arnauld in the 17th century and remained central to the entire philosophical tradition of "ideas" in the writings of Locke, Berkeley, Hume, Reid and Kant. However, the scholarly, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Is There Progress in Philosophy? The Case for Taking History Seriously.Peter P. Slezak - 2018 - Philosophy 93 (4):529-555.
    In response to widespread doubts among professional philosophers (Russell, Horwich, Dietrich, McGinn, Chalmers), Stoljar argues for a ‘reasonable optimism’ about progress in philosophy. He defends the large and surprising claim that ‘there is progress on all or reasonably many of the big questions.’ However, Stoljar’s caveats and admitted avoidance of historical evidence permits overlooking persistent controversies in philosophy of mind and cognitive science that are essentially unchanged since the 17th Century. Stoljar suggests that his claims are commonplace in philosophy departments (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Seeing truth or just seeming true?Adina Roskies - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):682-683.
  • Systematic, unconscious thought is the place to anchor quantum mechanics in the mind.Thomas Roeper - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):681-682.
  • Theory, concept, and experiment in the history of psychology: the older tradition behind a 'young science'.Edward S. Reed - 1989 - History of the Human Sciences 2 (3):333-356.
  • Berkeley's Ontology.David R. Raynor - 1987 - Dialogue 26 (4):611-620.
  • The emperor's old hat.Don Perlis - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):680-681.
  • The nonalgorithmic mind.Roger Penrose - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):692-705.
  • Precis of the emperor's new mind.Roger Penrose - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):643-705.
    The emperor's new mind (hereafter Emperor) is an attempt to put forward a scientific alternative to the viewpoint of according to which mental activity is merely the acting out of some algorithmic procedure. John Searle and other thinkers have likewise argued that mere calculation does not, of itself, evoke conscious mental attributes, such as understanding or intentionality, but they are still prepared to accept the action the brain, like that of any other physical object, could in principle be simulated by (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • Steadfast intentions.Keith K. Niall - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):679-680.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The powers of machines and minds.Chris Mortensen - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):678-679.
  • Computation and consciousness.Drew McDermott - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):676-678.
  • Lockean Empathy.Colin Marshall - 2016 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 54 (1):87-106.
    This paper offers an epistemic defense of empathy, drawing on John Locke's theory of ideas. Locke held that ideas of shape, unlike ideas of color, had a distinctive value: resembling qualities in their objects. I argue that the same is true of empathy, as when someone is pained by someone's pain. This means that empathy has the same epistemic value or objectivity that Locke and other early modern philosophers assigned to veridical perceptions of shape. For this to hold, pain and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Sense and Signification in Reid and Descartes: A Critique of Yolton's Reading.James W. Manns - 1997 - Dialogue 36 (3):511-526.
    RésuméLe but de cet article est de mettre en évidence les différences entre Descartes et Reid au sujet du rôle que chacun assigne aux sensations dans le processus perceptuel. Dans Perceptual Acquaintance, John Yolton ne trouve quepeu de choses dans les conceptions de Reid qui ne soient pas déjà de quelque façon présentes chez Descartes. Je soutiens au contraire que la théorie des sensations-comme-signes de Reid constitue un développement considérable par rapport à celle de Descartes ou à quoi que ce (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Gödel redux.Alexis Manaster-Ramer, Walter J. Savitch & Wlodek Zadrozny - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):675-676.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Uncertainty about quantum mechanics.Mark S. Madsen - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):674-675.
  • The discomforts of dualism.Bruce MacLennan - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):673-674.
  • Quantum AI.Rudi Lutz - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):672-673.
  • Time-delays in conscious processes.Benjamin Libet - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):672-672.
  • Parallelism and patterns of thought.R. W. Kentridge - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):670-671.
  • A long time ago in a computing lab far, far away….Jeffery L. Johnson, R. H. Ettinger & Timothy L. Hubbard - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):670-670.
  • Seeing dimensionally.J. F. M. Hunter - 1987 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 17 (September):553-566.
    John Locke:When we set before our eyes a round globe of uniform colour, v.g. gold, alabaster or jet, it is certain that the idea thereby imprinted in our mind is of a flat circle, variously shadowed, with several degrees of light and brightness coming to our eyes. But we having, by use, been accustomed to perceive what kind of appearance convex bodies are wont to make in us, what alterations are made in the reflections of light by the difference of (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Selecting for the con in consciousness.Deborah Hodgkin & Alasdair I. Houston - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):668-669.
  • Penrose's Platonism.James Higginbotham - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):667-668.
  • Outline of an Account of Experience.Anil Gupta - 2018 - Analytic Philosophy 59 (1):33-74.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Why you'll never know whether Roger Penrose is a computer.Clark Glymour & Kevin Kelly - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):666-667.
  • Where is the material of the emperor's mind?David L. Gilden & Joseph S. Lappin - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):665-666.
  • Strong AI and the problem of “second-order” algorithms.Gerd Gigerenzer - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):663-664.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Don't ask Plato about the emperor's mind.Alan Gamham - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):664-665.
  • Reality and the coloured points in Hume's treatise 1.Marina Frasca-Spada - 1997 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 5 (2):297-319.
  • Physics of brain-mind interaction.John C. Eccles - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):662-663.
  • Computations over abstract categories of representation.Roy Eagleson - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):661-662.
  • Perceptive questions about computation and cognition.Jon Doyle - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):661-661.
  • Betting your life on an algorithm.Daniel C. Dennett - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):660-661.
  • Is mathematical insight algorithmic?Martin Davis - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):659-660.
  • Computing the thinkable.David J. Chalmers - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):658-659.
  • Lucas revived? An undefended flank.Jeremy Butterfield - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):658-658.
  • AI and the Turing model of computation.Thomas M. Breuel - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):657-657.
  • Algorithms and physical laws.Franklin Boyle - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):656-657.
  • On “seeing” the truth of the Gödel sentence.George Boolos - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):655-656.
  • Intrinsic Multiperspectivity: Conceptual Forms and the Functional Architecture of the Perceptual System.Rainer Mausfeld - 2011 - In Welsch Wolfgang, Singer Wolf & Wunder Andre (eds.), Interdisciplinary Anthropology. Springer. pp. 19--54.
    It is a characteristic feature of our mental make-up that the same perceptual input situation can simultaneously elicit conflicting mental perspectives. This ability pervades our perceptual and cognitive domains. Striking examples are the dual character of pictures in picture perception, pretend play, or the ability to employ metaphors and allegories. I argue that traditional approaches, beyond being inadequate on principle grounds, are theoretically ill equipped to deal with these achievements. I then outline a theoretical perspective that has emerged from a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Locke on consciousness.Angela Coventry & Uriah Kriegel - 2008 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 25 (3):221-242.
    Locke’s theory of consciousness is often appropriated as a forerunner of present-day Higher-Order Perception (HOP) theories, but not much is said about it beyond that. We offer an interpretation of Locke’s account of consciousness that portrays it as crucially different from current-day HOP theory, both in detail and in spirit. In this paper, it is argued that there are good historical and philosophical reasons to attribute to Locke the view not that conscious states are accompanied by higher-order perceptions, but rather (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations