Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Descartes, modalities, and God.Gijsbert Van Den Brink - 1993 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 33 (1):1-15.
  • Revelation and the Nature of Colour.Keith Allen - 2011 - Dialectica 65 (2):153-176.
    According to naïve realist (or primitivist) theories of colour, colours are sui generis mind-independent properties. The question that I consider in this paper is the relationship of naïve realism to what Mark Johnston calls Revelation, the thesis that the essential nature of colour is fully revealed in a standard visual experience. In the first part of the paper, I argue that if naïve realism is true, then Revelation is false. In the second part of the paper, I defend naïve realism (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • A Função das Dúvidas Céticas nas Meditações de Descartes.Flavio Williges - 2007 - Doispontos 4 (2).
    Normal 0 21 The main goal of this paper is to maintain that the skeptical hypotheses in the First Meditation, and especially the doubt about material things, should be interpreted as a kind of mental exercise whose purpose is both to weaken our confidence in the senses and to prepare the reader of the Meditation for the learning of the truths accessible through the light of reason. Thus, the paper purports to show that in the economy of the Meditations skeptical (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Raffaella De Rosa's Descartes and the Puzzle of Sensory Representation.Tom Vinci - 2013 - Analytic Philosophy 54 (1):97-106.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Two kinds of necessity in Descartes: Conditional and absolute.Saniye Vatansever - 2017 - Filosofia Unisinos 18 (2).
    This paper attempts to resolve the apparent conflict between Descartes’ commitments to the creation doctrine and the necessity of eternal truths by elaborating different conceptions of necessity in Descartes’ framework. More specifically, I argue that the fact that Descartes concedes the necessity of eternal truths does not compel him to assert the impossibility of their negation. Necessity, for Descartes, rather means immutability. Descartes distinguishes two kinds of immutable truths. While truths about God’s essence are absolutely immutable, truths about the essences (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Descartes on Phantom Limbs.Tommy L. Lott - 1986 - Mind and Language 1 (3):243-271.
  • Cartesian Bodies.Alice Sowaal - 2004 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 34 (2):217 - 240.
    How we understand Descartes’s physics rests on how we interpret his ontological commitment to individual bodies, and in particular on how we account for their individuation. However, Descartes’s contemporaries as well as contemporary philosophers have seen Descartes’s account of the individuation of bodies as deeply flawed. In the first part of this paper, I discuss how the various problems and puzzles involved in Descartes’s account of the individuation of bodies arise, and the relevance of these problems for his physics. With (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Objective Being and “Ofness” in Descartes.Lionel Shapiro - 2011 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 84 (2):378-418.
    It is generally assumed that Descartes invokes “objective being in the intellect” in order to explain or describe an idea’s status as being “of something.” I argue that this assumption is mistaken. As emerges in his discussion of “materially false ideas” in the Fourth Replies, Descartes recognizes two senses of ‘idea of’. One, a theoretical sense, is itself introduced in terms of objective being. Hence Descartes can’t be introducing objective being to explain or describe “ofness” understood in this sense. Descartes (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The problem of mind-body interaction and the causal principle of Descartes’s Third Meditation.Dmytro Sepetyi - 2021 - Sententiae 40 (1):28-43.
    The article analyses recent English publications in Cartesian studies that deal with two problems: the problem of the intrinsic coherence of Descartes’s doctrine of the real distinction and interaction between mind and body and the problem of the consistency of this doctrine with the causal principle formulated in the Third Meditation. The principle at issue is alternatively interpreted by different Cartesian scholars either as the Hierarchy Principle, that the cause should be at least as perfect as its effects, or the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Relationship between the Notions of the Substantial Union and Interaction of Soul and Body in Descartes’ Philosophy.Dmytro Sepetyi - 2018 - Sententiae 37 (1):136-152.
    The author argues for the reductive interpretation of Descartes’ notion of the substantial union of soul and body, according to which the union is reduced to causal interactions. The opponents countered the reductive approach with the claims that Descartes (1) attributed sensations to the union rather than the soul; (2) held that the soul is the substantial form of the body; (3) identified some special conditions of the human body’s self-identity. In the article, the case is made that (a) these (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Descartes's Method of Doubt.Marleen Rozemond - 2004 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 34 (4):591-614.
    In Descartes's Method of Doubt Janet Broughton examines in depth Descartes's well-known use of the method of doubt in the Meditations. This is a very stimulating book. The book is rich in subtle, interesting ideas, and the writing is engaging in perhaps the best sense for philosophy. It is not only extremely lucid, but in addition one senses Broughton think the issues through on the page in a way that strongly draws the reader in. Broughton pursues the historian's aim of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Critical Notice of Janet Broughton, Descartes's Method of Doubt. [REVIEW]Marleen Rozemond - 2004 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 34 (4):591-613.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Divine simplicity and the eternal truths: Descartes and the scholastics.Andrew Pessin - 2010 - Philosophia 38 (1):69-105.
    Descartes famously endorsed the view that (CD) God freely created the eternal truths, such that He could have done otherwise than He did. This controversial doctrine is much discussed in recent secondary literature, yet Descartes’s actual arguments for CD have received very little attention. In this paper I focus on what many take to be a key Cartesian argument for CD: that divine simplicity entails the dependence of the eternal truths on the divine will. What makes this argument both important (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • First person illusions: Are they Descartes', or Kant's?Christopher Peacocke - 2012 - Philosophical Perspectives 26 (1):247-275.
  • Therapeutic Reflections on Our Bipolar History of Perception.Robert Pasnau - 2016 - Analytic Philosophy 57 (4):253-284.
    The long history of theorizing about perception divides into two quite distinct and irreconcilable camps, one that takes sensory experience to show us external reality just as it is, and one that takes such experience to reveal our own mind. I argue that we should reject both sides of this debate, and admit that the phenomenal character of experience, as such, reveals little about the nature of the external world and even less about the mind.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Ontological Argument as an Exercise in Cartesian Therapy.Lawrence Nolan - 2005 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 35 (4):521 - 562.
    I argue that Descartes intended the so-called ontological "argument" as a self-validating intuition, rather than as a formal proof. The textual evidence for this view is highly compelling, but the strongest support comes from understanding Descartes's diagnosis for why God's existence is not 'immediately' self-evident to everyone and the method of analysis that he develops for making it self-evident. The larger aim of the paper is to use the ontological argument as a case study of Descartes's nonformalist theory of deduction (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • La disparition des formes aristotéliciennes. À propos d'une démarche clandestine dans les Méditations.Georges Moyal - 2020 - Dialogue 59 (4):539-548.
    ABSTRACTThough the apprehension one may have of Aristotelian forms comes about from what Aristotle calls ‘induction,’ there is nothing necessary or intelligible to link together their components, as there is between the properties of matter. That is what leads René Descartes to rid the sciences of them surreptitiously in his VIth Meditation, and to make matter and its properties the common denominator of natural beings. The attempt is made in what follows to bring this move to light — a move (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Seriousness of Doubt and Our Natural Trust in the Senses in the First Meditation.David Macarthur - 2003 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 33 (2):159-181.
    In the present paper I shall argue that the real problem here is the very idea that there is a dilemma that compels us to choose sides. We can hold both that the meditator's doubts are fully serious, and that they leave the perspective of common sense largely unscathed. The key to dissolving the dilemma is to see that the meditator observes a distinction between two levels of epistemic standards: the very demanding standards appropriate to certainty, understood in a rather (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Why ‘non-mental’ won’t work: on Hempel’s dilemma and the characterization of the ‘physical’.Neal Judisch - 2008 - Philosophical Studies 140 (3):299 - 318.
    Recent discussions of physicalism have focused on the question how the physical ought to be characterized. Many have argued that any characterization of the physical should include the stipulation that the physical is non-mental, and others have claimed that a systematic substitution of ‘non-mental’ for ‘physical’ is all that is needed for philosophical purposes. I argue here that both claims are incorrect: substituting ‘non-mental’ for ‘physical’ in the causal argument for physicalism does not deliver the physicalist conclusion, and the specification (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Aristotle’s Philosophy of Mind.Alberto Jori - 2022 - Axiomathes 32 (6):1525-1538.
    In an attempt to reject Cartesian Dualism, some philosophers and scientists of the late twentieth century proposed a return to the ancient position that Descartes had opposed, i.e., Aristotle’s psychological hylomorphism, which applied to living beings the ontological thesis, according to which every substance is a compound of matter (hyle) and form (morphe). In this perspective, the soul is actual possession of the body’s capacity to perform a series of life functions. Therefore, according to Aristotle, soul and body are reciprocally (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Passions of the soul and Descartes’s machine psychology.Gary Hatfield - 2007 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 38 (1):1-35.
    Descartes developed an elaborate theory of animal physiology that he used to explain functionally organized, situationally adapted behavior in both human and nonhuman animals. Although he restricted true mentality to the human soul, I argue that he developed a purely mechanistic (or material) ‘psychology’ of sensory, motor, and low-level cognitive functions. In effect, he sought to mechanize the offices of the Aristotelian sensitive soul. He described the basic mechanisms in the Treatise on man, which he summarized in the Discourse. However, (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Reason, Nature, and God in Descartes.Gary Hatfield - 1989 - Science in Context 3 (1):175-201.
    This journal article has been superseded by a revised version, published in the collection _Essays on the Philosophy and Science of Rene Descartes_, ed. by Stephen Voss (Oxford University Press, 1993), 259–287.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Selbst- und Selbstlosigkeit.Michael Hampe - 2022 - Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 70 (5):795-808.
    Selflessness can be considered on an epistemic, on a moral, and on a historical level. The article follows recent thoughts by Jay L. Garfield on the idea that conceiving of oneself as a substantive self means following an illusion. It investigates the different senses of “illusion” and asks what it could mean for individuals and societies tobe transformed in such a way that this illusion would not play a role anymore.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Cartesian sensations.Raffaella De Rosa - 2009 - Philosophy Compass 4 (5):780-792.
    Descartes maintained that sensations of color and the like misrepresent the material world in normal circumstances. Some prominent scholars have argued that, to explain this Cartesian view, we must attribute to Descartes a causal account of sensory representation. I contend that neither the arguments motivating this reading nor the textual evidence offered in its support is sufficient to justify such attribution. Both textual and theoretical reasons point in the direction of an (at least partial) internalist account of Descartes' views on (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Constitutive A Priori.Graciela De Pierris - 1992 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 18 (sup1):179-214.
    The modem rationalist tradition initiated by Descartes has as one of its central tenets the independence of the human understanding from the senses. Regardless of the different ways in which independence from experience is understood, there is much common ground among the modem views on the a priori. Yet Kant, culminating this tradition, introduces an entirely new conception of the a priori never before articulated in the history of philosophy. This is the notion of elements in knowledge which are independent (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The Seriousness of Doubt and Our Natural Trust in the Senses in the First Meditation.MacArthur David - 2003 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 33 (2):159 - 181.
    In the Synopsis to the Meditations Descartes assures us that ‘extensive doubt… [provides] the easiest route by which the mind may be led away from the senses’. And in the Fifth Replies Descartes adds that it is essential to a proper understanding of the Meditations that ‘the entire testimony of the senses should be regarded as uncertain and even as false’. But to deny our ordinary trust in the senses on the grounds of such ‘hyperbolic’ or ‘metaphysical’ doubts as that (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • “The body I call ‘mine’ ”: A sense of bodily ownership in Descartes.Colin Chamberlain - 2019 - European Journal of Philosophy 27 (1):3-24.
    How does Descartes characterize the peculiar way in which each of us is aware of our bodies? I argue that Descartes recognizes a sense of bodily ownership, such that the body sensorily appears to be one's own in bodily awareness. This sensory appearance of ownership is ubiquitous, for Descartes, in that bodily awareness always confers a sense of ownership. This appearance is confused, in so far as bodily awareness simultaneously represents the subject as identical to, partially composed by, and united (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Abstraction and the Real Distinction Between Mind and Body.Bruce M. Thomas - 1995 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 25 (1):83-101.
    Descartes contends that he, or his mind, is really distinct from his body. Many philosophers have little patience with this claim. What could be more obvious than that the mind depends on the body? But their impatience often dissolves when they recognize that Descartes only asserts a de re modal statement. To say that one thing is really distinct from another is to say that each can exist apart from the other. But should we grant Descartes this de re modal (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Descartes and Hume on I-thoughts.Luca Forgione - 2018 - Thémata: Revista de Filosofía 57:211-228.
    Self-consciousness can be understood as the ability to think I-thou-ghts which can be described as thoughts about oneself ‘as oneself’. Self-consciousness possesses two specific correlated features: the first regards the fact that it is grounded on a first-person perspective, whereas the second concerns the fact that it should be considered a consciousness of the self as subject rather than a consciousness of the self as object. The aim of this paper is to analyse a few considerations about Descartes and Hume’s (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Uno intuitu videmus: La naturaleza del conocimiento intuitivo en Spinoza a la luz de Descartes.Mario Narváez - 2017 - Revista Latinoamericana de Filosofia 43 (2):159-181.
    Generalmente los comentadores han abordado la temática de la intuición en la filosofía de Spinoza desde la perspectiva de la problemática de lo que en la Ética aparece como ciencia intuitiva o tercer genero de conocimiento. En el presente artículo, en cambio, intentamos mostrar que hay en los escritos de Spinoza un concepto de intuición más amplio que el que está implícito en la ciencia intuitiva, del cual esta no sería más que una subespecie. Como paso previo para alcanzar dicho (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Descartes: Libertarianist, necessitarianist, actualist?Timo Kajamies - 2005 - Minerva - An Internet Journal of Philosophy 9 (1).
    According to necessitarianism, all truths are logically necessary, and the modal doctrine of a necessitarian philosopher is in a sharp contrast with something that seems manifest—the view that there are contingent truths. At least on the face of it, then, necessitarianism is highly implausible. René Descartes is usually not regarded as a necessitarian philosopher, but some of his philosophical views raise the worry as to whether he is committed to the necessity of all truths. This paper is an appraisal of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • O problema da coerência na correspondência entre Espinosa e Oldenburg.Fernando Bonadia de Oliveira - 2015 - Filosofia Do Renascimento E Século XVI (Coleção XVI Encontro Anpof).
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Conceivability and Possibility — Conceivability as an Epistemic Guide to Possibility.Feng Shuyi - 2017 - Dissertation, Ruprecht-Karls-Universität Heidelberg
    In this dissertation, I evaluate whether conceivability can be regarded as an epistemic guide to possibility.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Bodily awareness and the self.Bill Brewer - 1995 - In Jose Luis Bermudez, Anthony J. Marcel & Naomi M. Eilan (eds.), The Body and the Self. Cambridge: Mass: Mit Press. pp. 291-€“303.
    In The Varieties of Reference (1982), Gareth Evans claims that considerations having to do with certain basic ways we have of gaining knowledge of our own physical states and properties provide "the most powerful antidote to a Cartesian conception of the self" (220). In this chapter, I start with a discussion and evaluation of Evans' own argument, which is, I think, in the end unconvincing. Then I raise the possibility of a more direct application of similar considerations in defence of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations