Switch to: References

Citations of:

Do human cells have rights?

Bioethics 1 (1):1-14 (1987)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Potentiality switches and epistemic uncertainty: the Argument from Potential in times of human embryo-like structures.Ana M. Pereira Daoud, Wybo J. Dondorp, Annelien L. Bredenoord & Guido M. W. R. De Wert - 2024 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 27 (1):37-48.
    Recent advancements in developmental biology enable the creation of embryo-like structures from human stem cells, which we refer to as human embryo-like structures (hELS). These structures provide promising tools to complement—and perhaps ultimately replace—the use of human embryos in clinical and fundamental research. But what if these hELS—when further improved—also have a claim to moral status? What would that imply for their research use? In this paper, we explore these questions in relation to the traditional answer as to why human (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Potentiality Argument in the Debate relating to the Beginning of Personhood.Werner Wolbert - 2000 - Human Reproduction and Genetic Ethics 6 (2):19-26.
    (2000). The Potentiality Argument in the Debate relating to the Beginning of Personhood. Human Reproduction & Genetic Ethics: Vol. 6, No. 2, pp. 19-26.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On Moral Nose.Fabrizio Turoldo - 2024 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 33 (1):102-111.
    There are many authors who consider the so-called “moral nose” a valid epistemological tool in the field of morality. The expression was used by George Orwell, following in Friedrich Nietzsche’s footsteps and was very clearly described by Leo Tolstoy. It has also been employed by authors such as Elisabeth Anscombe, Bernard Williams, Noam Chomsky, Stuart Hampshire, Mary Warnock, and Leon Kass. This article examines John Harris’ detailed criticism of what he ironically calls the “olfactory school of moral philosophy.” Harris’ criticism (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Totipotency and the value of embryonic cells.Christopher W. Tindale - 1994 - Journal of Value Inquiry 28 (4):519-528.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Genetic Technologies and Sport: The New Ethical Issue.Andy Miah - 2001 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 28 (1):32-52.
  • From Sancitity to Screening: Genetic Disabilities, Risk and Rhetorical Strategies in Wrongful Birth and Wrongful Conception Cases. [REVIEW]Robin Mackenzie - 1999 - Feminist Legal Studies 7 (2):175-191.
    This analysis scrutinises the rhetorical strategies used by judges in wrongful life and wrongful birth actions as evidence for the assertion that the judicial reading of public policy in such cases has undergone a significant shift which is likely to accelerate as genetic knowledge grows and health care resources shrink. The implications of the predicted move towards increased genetic testing of prospective parents are traversed in relation to feminist analyses of the impact of genetics on reproductive technology. These are viewed (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Otherness, Cloning, and Morality in John Wyndham’s The Midwich Cuckoos (1957).Solveig Lena Hansen - 2021 - Journal of Medical Humanities 43 (4):547-560.
    The British writer John Wyndham (1903–1969) explored societal effects of surprising or mystical events. A paradigmatic example is _The Midwich Cuckoos_ (1957), which portrays identical-looking children born without sexual intercourse. I propose a reading strategy that focuses on the fictional spatial order and analyses how the construction of the children’s otherness interferes with the village’s demarcation. Furthermore, I interpret the mysterious pregnancies as a reference to basic embryo research in the 1950s – cloning. Finally, I scrutinize Wyndham’s negotiation of utilitarianism (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The bioethical structure of a human being.Paul Copland & Grant Gillett - 2003 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 20 (2):123–131.
    Bioethical debates such as those surrounding the manipulation of human embryos are often based on metaphysical assumptions that lack a foundation in the natural sciences. In this paper we support a gradualist position whereby the embryo progressively takes on the form and associated ethical significance of a human being. We support this position by introducing a concept of biological structure or form to show how the gradualist position has its metaphysical foundations in modern biology. The conceptual basis for form and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • In the world of Dolly, when does a human embryo acquire respect?C. Cameron - 2005 - Journal of Medical Ethics 31 (4):215-220.
    For most of the 20th century, it was possible to regard fertilisation as the identifiable point when life begins, because this moment could be defined unequivocally and was thought to be the single most essential biological step in the establishment of a new human entity. Since the successful reproductive cloning of Dolly and other mammals, it is clear that any human cell has the potential to supply the full genome of an embryo, and hence a person, without going through fertilisation. (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Why we should not extend the 14-day rule.Bruce Philip Blackshaw & Daniel Rodger - 2021 - Journal of Medical Ethics (10):712-714.
    The 14-day rule restricts the culturing of human embryos in vitro for the purposes of scientific research for no longer than 14 days. Since researchers recently developed the capability to exceed the 14-day limit, pressure to modify the rule has started to build. Sophia McCully argues that the limit should be extended to 28 days, listing numerous potential benefits of doing so. We contend that McCully has not engaged with the main reasons why the Warnock Committee set such a limit, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority: Evidence Based Policy Formation in a Contested Context.Angus Dawson - 2004 - Health Care Analysis 12 (1):1-6.
    This article briefly reviews the various papers contained in this volume. They were originally presented at a research workshop held at Keele University in the UK in February 2003. It is suggested that the different papers raise a series of related legal, social and ethical issues and can be collectively seen to demonstrate the fact that policy formation in relation to reproductive matters is highly contested. It is concluded that ethical policy formation in this area needs to be based on (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Philosophy, medicine and its technologies.B. Almond - 1988 - Journal of Medical Ethics 14 (4):173-178.
    There is a need to bring ethics and medical practice closer together, despite the risk and problems this may involve. Deontological ethics may promote sanctity of life considerations against the quality of life considerations favoured by consequentialists or utilitarians; while talk of respect for life and the value of life may point to more qualified ethical positions. This paper argues for a respect-for-life position, dismissing a utilitarian cost-benefit outlook as too simplistic; but an unqualified fixed principles approach is also ruled (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations