Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. In the shadows of the löwenheim-Skolem theorem: Early combinatorial analyses of mathematical proofs.Jan von Plato - 2007 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 13 (2):189-225.
    The Löwenheim-Skolem theorem was published in Skolem's long paper of 1920, with the first section dedicated to the theorem. The second section of the paper contains a proof-theoretical analysis of derivations in lattice theory. The main result, otherwise believed to have been established in the late 1980s, was a polynomial-time decision algorithm for these derivations. Skolem did not develop any notation for the representation of derivations, which makes the proofs of his results hard to follow. Such a formal notation is (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Formalization of Hilbert's geometry of incidence and parallelism.Jan von Plato - 1997 - Synthese 110 (1):127-141.
    Three things are presented: How Hilbert changed the original construction postulates of his geometry into existential axioms; In what sense he formalized geometry; How elementary geometry is formalized to present day's standards.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Constructivity in Geometry.Richard Vesley - 1999 - History and Philosophy of Logic 20 (3-4):291-294.
    We review and contrast three ways to make up a formal Euclidean geometry which one might call constructive, in a computational sense. The starting point is the first-order geometry created by Tarski.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Formalization of Hilbert's geometry of incidence and parallelism.Jan Platvono - 1997 - Synthese 110 (1):127-141.
    Three things are presented: How Hilbert changed the original construction postulates of his geometry into existential axioms; In what sense he formalized geometry; How elementary geometry is formalized to present day's standards.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Axiomatizing geometric constructions.Victor Pambuccian - 2008 - Journal of Applied Logic 6 (1):24-46.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Constructive geometrical reasoning and diagrams.John Mumma - 2012 - Synthese 186 (1):103-119.
    Modern formal accounts of the constructive nature of elementary geometry do not aim to capture the intuitive or concrete character of geometrical construction. In line with the general abstract approach of modern axiomatics, nothing is presumed of the objects that a geometric construction produces. This study explores the possibility of a formal account of geometric construction where the basic geometric objects are understood from the outset to possess certain spatial properties. The discussion is centered around Eu , a recently developed (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • A common axiom set for classical and intuitionistic plane geometry.Melinda Lombard & Richard Vesley - 1998 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 95 (1-3):229-255.
    We describe a first order axiom set which yields the classical first order Euclidean geometry of Tarski when used with classical logic, and yields an intuitionistic Euclidean geometry when used with intuitionistic logic. The first order language has a single six place atomic predicate and no function symbols. The intuitionistic system has a computational interpretation in recursive function theory, that is, a realizability interpretation analogous to those given by Kleene for intuitionistic arithmetic and analysis. This interpretation shows the unprovability in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Using the prover ANDP to simplify orthogonality.Dafa Li - 2003 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 124 (1-3):49-70.
    In the 1920s, Heyting attempted at axiomatizing constructive geometry. Recently, von Plato used different concepts to axiomatize the geometry: he used 14 axioms to describe the axiomatization for apartness geometry. Then he added axioms A1 and A2 to his apartness geometry to get his affine geometry, then he added axioms O1, O2, O3 and O4 to the affine geometry to get orthogonality. In total, this gives 22 axioms. von Plato used four relations to describe the concept of orthogonality in O1, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Simplifying von Plato's axiomatization of Constructive Apartness Geometry.Dafa Li, Peifa Jia & Xinxin Li - 2000 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 102 (1-2):1-26.
    In the 1920s Heyting attempted at axiomatizing constructive geometry. Recently, von Plato used different concepts to axiomatize it. He used 14 axioms to formulate constructive apartness geometry, seven of which have occurrences of negation. In this paper we show with the help of ANDP, a theorem prover based on natural deduction, that four new axioms without negation, shorter and more intuitive, can replace seven of von Plato's 14 ones. Thus we obtained a near negation-free new system consisting of 11 axioms.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Constructive geometry and the parallel postulate.Michael Beeson - 2016 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 22 (1):1-104.
    Euclidean geometry, as presented by Euclid, consists of straightedge-and-compass constructions and rigorous reasoning about the results of those constructions. We show that Euclidean geometry can be developed using only intuitionistic logic. This involves finding “uniform” constructions where normally a case distinction is used. For example, in finding a perpendicular to line L through point p, one usually uses two different constructions, “erecting” a perpendicular when p is on L, and “dropping” a perpendicular when p is not on L, but in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A formal system for euclid’s elements.Jeremy Avigad, Edward Dean & John Mumma - 2009 - Review of Symbolic Logic 2 (4):700--768.
    We present a formal system, E, which provides a faithful model of the proofs in Euclid's Elements, including the use of diagrammatic reasoning.
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • A ModalWalk Through Space.Marco Aiello & Johan van Benthem - 2002 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 12 (3-4):319-363.
    We investigate the major mathematical theories of space from a modal standpoint: topology, affine geometry, metric geometry, and vector algebra. This allows us to see new fine-structure in spatial patterns which suggests analogies across these mathematical theories in terms of modal, temporal, and conditional logics. Throughout the modal walk through space, expressive power is analyzed in terms of language design, bisimulations, and correspondence phenomena. The result is both unification across the areas visited, and the uncovering of interesting new questions.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations