Switch to: References

Citations of:

Independence friendly logic

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2010)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. A cirquent calculus system with clustering and ranking.Wenyan Xu - 2016 - Journal of Applied Logic 16:37-49.
  • Game Semantics, Quantifiers and Logical Omniscience.Bruno Ramos Mendonça - forthcoming - Logic and Logical Philosophy:1-22.
    Logical omniscience states that the knowledge set of ordinary rational agents is closed for its logical consequences. Although epistemic logicians in general judge this principle unrealistic, there is no consensus on how it should be restrained. The challenge is conceptual: we must find adequate criteria for separating obvious logical consequences from non-obvious ones. Non-classical game-theoretic semantics has been employed in this discussion with relative success. On the one hand, with urn semantics [15], an expressive fragment of classical game semantics that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Philosophical Problems of Foundations of Logic.Alexander S. Karpenko - 2014 - Studia Humana 3 (1):13-26.
    In the paper the following questions are discussed: What is logical consequence? What are logical constants? What is a logical system? What is logical pluralism? What is logic? In the conclusion, the main tendencies of development of modern logic are pointed out.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hintikka’s Take on the Axiom of Choice and the Constructivist Challenge.Radmila Jovanović - 2013 - Revista de Humanidades de Valparaíso 2:135-150.
    In the present paper we confront Martin- Löf’s analysis of the axiom of choice with J. Hintikka’s standing on this axiom. Hintikka claims that his game theoretical semantics for Independence Friendly Logic justifies Zermelo’s axiom of choice in a first-order way perfectly acceptable for the constructivists. In fact, Martin- Löf’s results lead to the following considerations:Hintikka preferred version of the axiom of choice is indeed acceptable for the constructivists and its meaning does not involve higher order logic.However, the version acceptable (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Supervenience, Dependence, Disjunction.Lloyd Humberstone - forthcoming - Logic and Logical Philosophy:1.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The Paradox Paradox Non-Paradox and Conjunction Fallacy Non-Fallacy.Noah Greenstein - 2023 - Australasian Journal of Logic 20 (3):478-489.
    Brock and Glasgow recently introduced a new definition of paradox and argue that this conception of paradox itself leads to paradox, the so-called Paradox Paradox. I show that they beg the questions during the course of their argument, but, more importantly, do so in a philosophically interesting way: it reveals a counterexample to the equivalence between being a logical truth and having a probability of one. This has consequences regarding norms of rationality, undermining the grounds for the Conjunction Fallacy.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Inclusion and exclusion dependencies in team semantics—on some logics of imperfect information.Pietro Galliani - 2012 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 163 (1):68-84.
  • Logics for Analyzing Games.Johan Van Benthem & Dominik Klein - 2019 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Locke and Leibniz on the Balance of Reasons.Markku Roinila - 2013 - In Dana Riesenfeld & Giovanni Scarafile (eds.), Perspectives on Theory of Controversies and the Ethics of Communication. Springer. pp. 49-57.
    One of the features of John Locke’s moral philosophy is the idea that morality is based on our beliefs concerning the future good. In An Essay Concerning Human Understanding II, xxi, §70, Locke argues that we have to decide between the probability of afterlife and our present temptations. In itself, this kind of decision model is not rare in Early Modern philosophy. Blaise Pascal’s Wager is a famous example of a similar idea of balancing between available options which Marcelo Dascal (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark