Switch to: References

Citations of:

Grotius, Carneades and Hobbes

Grotiana 4 (1):43-62 (1983)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Hobbes's Fool the Stultus, Grotius, and the Epicurean Tradition.Patricia Springborg - 2010 - Hobbes Studies 23 (1):29-53.
    Among the paradoxical aspects of Hobbes's scepticism attention has recently turned to Hobbes's fool of Leviathan , chapter xv, where Hobbes makes a claim about justice that paraphrases Psalm 52:1: "The fool hath said in his heart there is no God." It is a charge of which Hobbes himself could be suspected, but in fact we see that it is on this startling claim that his legal positivism rests. Moreover it is embedded in a theory of natural law that Hobbes (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The actual and another modernity. Order and imagination in Don Quixote.Raymond Geuss - 2008 - History of European Ideas 34 (1):14-25.
  • Hugo Grotius, ceticismo moral e o uso de argumentos in utramque partem.Marcelo de Araujo - 2011 - Veritas – Revista de Filosofia da Pucrs 56 (3):145-166.
    O uso de argumentos igualmente convincentes tanto em prol quanto contra a veracidade de uma proposição era conhecido na Renascença como in utramque partem. Céticos do início da Modernidade utilizaram argumentos in utramque partem visando demonstrar que não se pode fundamentar a moralidade em um terreno sólido, já que os argumentos apresentados em favor da ideia de Justiça poderiam ser neutralizados por argumentos igualmente convincentes contra a ideia de Justiça. Nesse artigo, eu argumento que Hugo Grotius tentou refutar esse tipo (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Written on the heart: on the grounds of moral obligation in natural law theory.Christian Daru - 2017 - International Journal of Philosophy and Theology 78 (3):200-214.
    The extent to which God grounds normativity within natural law theory is analyzed. I examine Hugo Grotius’s understanding of natural law and human nature and show that Grotius makes few explicit metaphysical commitments which makes his view open to development in at least two different ways. Then a Thomistic view of natural law and human nature is developed. It is shown that Grotius’s position could be developed as a proto-new natural law theory, but this leaves it open to powerful objections (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hugo grotius.Jon Miller - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Hugo Grotius (1583-1645) [Hugo, Huigh or Hugeianus de Groot] was a towering figure in philosophy, law, political theory and associated fields during the seventeenth century and for hundreds of years afterwards. His work ranged over a wide array of topics, though he is best known to philosophers today for his contributions to the natural law theories of normativity which emerged in the later medieval and early modern periods. This article will attempt to explain his views on the law of nature (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Informed consent: its origins, purpose, problems, and limits.Nancy M. Kettle - unknown
    The doctrine of informed consent, defined as respect for autonomy, is the tool used to govern the relationship between physicians and patients. Its framework relies on rights and duties that mark these relationships. The main purpose of informed consent is to promote human rights and dignity. Some researchers claim that informed consent has successfully replaced patients' historical predispositions to accept physicians' advice without much explicit resistance. Although the doctrine of informed consent promotes ideals worth pursuing, a successful implementation of these (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • self-love and sociability: the 'rudiments of commerce' in the state of nature.Peter Xavier Price - 2018 - Modern Intellectual History.
    Istvan Hont’s classic work on the theoretical links between the seventeenth-century natural jurists Hugo Grotius and Samuel Pufendorf and the eighteenth-century Scottish political economists remains a popular trope among intellectual and economic historians of various stamps. Despite this, a common criticism levelled at Hont remains his relative lack of engagement with the relationship between religion and economics in the early modern period. This paper challenges this aspect of Hont’s narrative by drawing attention to an alternative, albeit complementary, assessment of the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark