Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Whose Sovereignty? Empire Versus International Law.Jean L. Cohen - 2004 - Ethics and International Affairs 18 (3):1-24.
    This article focuses on the impact of globalization on international law and the discourse of sovereignty. It challenges the claim that we have entered into a new world order characterized by transnational governance and decentered global law, which have replaced “traditional” international law and rendered the concepts of state sovereignty and international society anachronistic. We are indeed in the presence of something new. But if we drop the concept of sovereignty and buy into the idea that transnational governance has upstaged (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • The Liberal Constitution and Foreign Affairs.Fernando R. Tesón - 2011 - Social Philosophy and Policy 28 (1):115-149.
    Scholars have debated the meaning of the foreign-relations clauses in the U.S. Constitution. This essay attempts to outline the foreign-relations clauses that an ideal constitution should have. A liberal constitution must enable the government to implement a morally defensible foreign policy. The first priority is the defense of liberty. The constitution must allow the government to effectively defend persons, territory, and liberal institutions themselves. The liberal government should also contribute to the advancement of global freedom, subject to a number of (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Humanitarian vigilantes or legal entrepreneurs: Enforcing human rights in international society.Nicholas J. Wheeler - 2000 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 3 (1):139-162.
  • The Rawlsian theory of international law.Fernando R. Tesón - 1995 - Ethics and International Affairs 9:79–99.
    Teson critiques a recent article by John Rawls in which Rawls extends his acclaimed political theory to include international relations.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Self-Defense in International Law and Rights of Persons.Fernando R. Tesón - 2004 - Ethics and International Affairs 18 (1):87-91.
  • Humanitarian intervention: Loose ends.Fernando R. Tesón - 2011 - Journal of Military Ethics 10 (3):192-212.
    Abstract The article addresses three aspects of the humanitarian intervention doctrine. It argues, first, that the value of sovereignty rests on the justified social processes of the target state ? the horizontal contract. Foreign interventions, even when otherwise justified, must respect the horizontal contract. In contrast, morally objectionable social processes (such as the subjection of women) are not protected by sovereignty (intervention, of course, may be banned for other reasons). In addition, tyrants have no moral protection against interventions directed at (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Enabling Monsters: A Reply to Professor Miller.Fernando R. Tesón - 2011 - Ethics and International Affairs 25 (2):165-182.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Selective Humanitarian Intervention: Moral Reason and Collective Agents.Jennifer Szende - 2012 - Journal of Global Ethics 8 (1):63-76.
    This paper examines four interpretations of the observation that humanitarian intervention might be used ‘selectively’ or ‘inconsistently’ in order to elucidate the normative commitments of the deliberative process in international relations. The paper argues that there are several types of concerns that are implicit in the accusation of inconsistency, and only some of them amount to objections to humanitarian intervention as a whole. The paradox of humanitarian intervention is that intervention is prohibited except where the intervention is humanitarian, yet humanitarian (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Revolution and Intervention.Massimo Renzo - 2019 - Noûs 54 (1):233-253.
    Provided that traditional jus ad bellum principles are fulfilled, military humanitarian intervention to stop large scale violations of human rights (such as genocide, crimes against humanity or war crimes) is widely regarded as morally permissible. In cases of “supreme humanitarian emergency”, not only are the victims morally permitted to rebel, but other states are also permitted to militarily intervene. Things are different if the human rights violations in question fall short of supreme humanitarian emergency. Because of the importance of respecting (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • La soberanía como responsabilidad y los fundamentos del nuevo intervencionismo humanitario.Luis Felipe Piedrahita Ramírez - 2015 - Estudios de Filosofía (Universidad de Antioquia) 51.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • State prerogatives, civil society, and liberalization: The paradoxes of the late twentieth century in the third world.Mahmood Monshipouri - 1997 - Ethics and International Affairs 11:233–251.
    Monshipouri examines three paradoxes in the conflict between the legal-political global order and the growth of civil society in the international system: state-building vs. democratization; economic liberalization vs. political liberalization; and human rights vs. state sovereignty.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Forced to be Free: Rethinking J. S. Mill and Intervention.J. Joseph Miller - 2005 - Politics and Ethics Review 1 (2):119-137.
  • Humanitarian intervention: Three ethical positions.Pierre Laberge - 1995 - Ethics and International Affairs 9:15–35.
    LaBerge examines the ethical positions of Rawls, Kant, John Walzer adapted from J. S. Mill, and Canadian philosopher Howard Adelman are, and writes that they constitute "an ethics of human rights, ethics of the right to a historical community, and an ethics of peace.".
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Legitimacy, humanitarian intervention, and international institutions.Miles Kahler - 2011 - Politics, Philosophy and Economics 10 (1):20-45.
    The legitimacy of humanitarian intervention has been contested for more than a century, yet pressure for such intervention persists. Normative evolution and institutional design have been closely linked since the first debates over humanitarian intervention more than a century ago. Three norms have competed in shaping state practice and the normative discourse: human rights, peace preservation, and sovereignty. The rebalancing of these norms over time, most recently as the state’s responsibility to protect, has reflected specific international institutional environments. The contemporary (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Whose Responsibility to Protect? The Duties of Humanitarian Intervention.James Pattison - 2008 - Journal of Military Ethics 7 (4):262-283.
    The International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty's report, The Responsibility to Protect, argues that when a state is unable or unwilling to uphold its citizens? basic human rights, such as in cases of genocide, ethnic cleansing, and crimes against humanity, the international community has a responsibility to protect these citizens by undertaking humanitarian intervention. An essential issue, however, remains unresolved: which particular agent in the international community has the duty to intervene? In this article, I critically examine four ways (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Humanitarian Intervention and International Law: The Moral Importance of an Intervener’s Legal Status.James Pattison - 2007 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 10 (3):301-319.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Who Should Intervene?Fredrik D. Hjorthen - 2017 - Res Publica 23 (4):391-407.
    The objective of this paper is to develop a novel account of how the duty to undertake humanitarian intervention should be assigned to states. It takes as its point of departure two worries about the best existing answer to this question, namely: that it is insensitive to historical considerations, and that its distribution is unfair. Against this background I propose that the duty to intervene should be assigned to states based on the strength of their claim to reject the burden (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Humanitarian intervention and historical responsibility.Fredrik D. Hjorthen & Göran Duus-Otterström - 2016 - Journal of Global Ethics 12 (2):187-203.
    ABSTRACTSome suggest that the duty of humanitarian intervention should be discharged by states that are historically responsible for the occurrence of violence. A fundamental problem with this suggestion is that historically responsible states might be ill-suited to intervene because they are unlikely to enjoy support from the local population. Cécile Fabre has suggested a way around that problem, arguing that responsible states ought to pay for humanitarian interventions even though they ought not to take part in the military operations. We (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The New Utopianism: Liberalism, American Foreign Policy, and the War in Iraq.Eric A. Heinze - 2008 - Journal of International Political Theory 4 (1):105-125.
    This article explores the extent to which the decision to invade Iraq in 2003 coheres with the normative precepts of liberalism as an international political theory. Beginning with a Lockean liberal theory of the state, this article first examines the evolution of international liberalism in order to identify the fundamental normative postulates of liberal theory as it pertains to international relations, especially regarding the use of military force. The article then advances two interrelated arguments: First, that the underpinnings of the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Rawlsian Theory of International Law.Fernando R. Teson - 1995 - Ethics International Affairs 9 (1):79-99.
    Teson critiques a recent article by John Rawls in which Rawls extends his acclaimed political theory to include international relations.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Eight Principles for Humanitarian Intervention.Fernando R. Tesón - 2006 - Journal of Military Ethics 5 (2):93-113.
    When is humanitarian intervention legitimate and how should such interventions be conducted? This article sets out eight liberal principles that underlie humanitarian intervention, some of them abstract principles of international ethics and others more concrete principles that apply specifically to humanitarian intervention. It argues that whilst these principles do not determine the legitimacy of particular interventions, they should ?incline? our judgments towards approval or disapproval. The basic principles include the liberal idea that governments are the mere agents of the people, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Commonsense morality and the consequentialist ethics of humanitarian intervention.Eric A. Heinze - 2005 - Journal of Military Ethics 4 (3):168-182.
    Abstract Finding a moral justification for humanitarian intervention has been the objective of a great deal of academic inquiry in recent years. Most of these treatments, however, make certain arguments or assumptions about the morality of humanitarian intervention without fully exploring their precise philosophical underpinnings, which has led to an increasingly disjointed body of literature. The purpose of this essay, therefore, is to suggest that the conventional arguments and assumptions made about the morality of humanitarian intervention can be encompassed in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Rebellion, Humanitarian Intervention, and the Prudential Constraints on War.Ned Dobos - 2008 - Journal of Military Ethics 7 (2):102-115.
    Both radical rebellion and humanitarian intervention aim to defend citizens against tyranny and human rights abuses at the hands of their government. The only difference is that rebellion is waged by the oppressed subjects themselves, while humanitarian intervention is carried out by foreigners on their behalf. In this paper, it is argued that the prudential constraints on war (last resort, probability of success, and proportionality) impose tighter restrictions on, or demand more of, humanitarian interveners than they do of rebels. Specifically, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Is U.N. Security Council Authorisation for Armed Humanitarian Intervention Morally Necessary?Ned Dobos - 2010 - Philosophia 38 (3):499-515.
    Relative to the abundance of literature devoted to the legal significance of UN authorisation, little has been written about whether the UN’s failure to sanction an intervention can ever make it immoral. This is the question that I take up here. I argue that UN authorisation (or lack thereof) can have some indirect bearing on the moral status of a humanitarian intervention. That is, it can affect whether an intervention satisfies other widely accepted justifying conditions, such as proportionality, “internal” legitimacy, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Proportionality in modern just war theory: A tort-based approach.Davis Brown - 2011 - Journal of Military Ethics 10 (3):213-229.
    Abstract This article lays a theoretical foundation the perspective of international law for applying the principle of proportionality of cause in modern just war theory. It proposes an analytical framework for measuring proportionality based on general tort law, filtered through the international law of state responsibility. It proposes assessing the use of force as a proportionate (or disproportionate) remediation for an injury (present or future) caused by another state that is in breach of its legal obligations. The article then applies (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The UN Security Council and the Question of Humanitarian Intervention in Darfur.Alex Bellamy & Paul Williams - 2006 - Journal of Military Ethics 5 (2):144-160.
    This article explores the different moral and legal arguments used by protagonists in the debate about whether or not to conduct a humanitarian intervention in Darfur. The first section briefly outlines four moral and legal positions on whether there is (and should be) a right and/or duty of humanitarian intervention: communitarianism, restrictionist and counter-restrictionist legal positivism and liberal cosmopolitanism. The second section then provides an overview of the Security Council's debate about responding to Darfur's crisis, showing how its policy was (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Motives, outcomes, intent and the legitimacy of humanitarian intervention.Alex J. Bellamy - 2004 - Journal of Military Ethics 3 (3):216-232.
    During the 1990s, international society increasingly recognised that states who abuse their citizens in the most egregious ways ought to lose their sovereign inviolability and be subject to humanitarian intervention. The emergence of this norm has given renewed significance to the debate concerning what it is about humanitarian intervention that makes it legitimate. The most popular view is that it is humanitarian motivations that legitimise intervention. Others insist that humanitarian outcomes are more important that an actor's motivations, pointing for instance (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations