Switch to: References

Citations of:

S. Leśniewski's Calculus of Names

In Jan T. J. Srzednicki, V. F. Rickey & J. Czelakowski (eds.), Studia Logica. Distributors for the United States and Canada, Kluwer Boston. pp. 59--122 (1984)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Leśniewski's foundations of mathematics.Vito F. Sinisi - 1983 - Topoi 2 (1):3-52.
    During 1927-1931 Leśniewski published a series of articles (169 pages) entitled 'O podstawach matematyki' [On the Foundations of Mathematics] in the journal Przeglad Filozoficzny [Philosophical Review], and an abridged English translation of this series is presented here. With the exception of this work, all of Leśniewski's publications appearing after the first World War were written in German, and hence accessible to scholars and logicians in the West. This work, however, since written in Polish, has heretofore not been accessible to most (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The development of ontology.Vito F. Sinisi - 1983 - Topoi 2 (1):53-61.
  • Rejection in Łukasiewicz's and Słupecki's Sense.Urszula Wybraniec-Skardowska - 2018 - In Urszula Wybraniec-Skardowska & Ángel Garrido (eds.), The Lvov-Warsaw School. Past and Present. Cham, Switzerland: Springer- Birkhauser,. pp. 575-597.
    The idea of rejection originated by Aristotle. The notion of rejection was introduced into formal logic by Łukasiewicz [20]. He applied it to complete syntactic characterization of deductive systems using an axiomatic method of rejection of propositions [22, 23]. The paper gives not only genesis, but also development and generalization of the notion of rejection. It also emphasizes the methodological approach to biaspectual axiomatic method of characterization of deductive systems as acceptance (asserted) systems and rejection (refutation) systems, introduced by Łukasiewicz (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Reism and Le'sniewski's Ontology.Jan Woleński - 1986 - History and Philosophy of Logic 7 (2):167-176.
    This paper examines relations between reism, the metaphysical theory invented by Tadeusz Kotarbi?ski, and Le?niewski's calculus of names. It is shown that Kotarbi?ski's interpretation of common nouns as genuine names, i.e. names of things is essentially based on Le?niewski's logical ideas. It is pointed out that Le?niewskian semantics offers better prospects for nominalism than does semantics of the standard firstorder predicate calculus.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • A finite approximation to models of set theory.Paul Weingartner - 1975 - Studia Logica 34 (1):45 - 58.
  • The Ontological Law of Contradiction and Its Logical Structure.Toshiharu Waragai - 1981 - Annals of the Japan Association for Philosophy of Science 6 (1):43-58.
  • Ontological Burden of Grammatical Categories.Toshiharu Waragai - 1979 - Annals of the Japan Association for Philosophy of Science 5 (4):185-205.
  • Ontology Based on Non-reflexive Identity and Product Name Functor.Toshiharu Waragai - 1987 - Annals of the Japan Association for Philosophy of Science 7 (2):73-84.
  • “∊” and Common Names.Vito F. Sinisi - 1965 - Philosophy of Science 32 (3/4):281-.
    In [6] I tried to show how an objection to “the nominalist's” analysis of “This is red” and “That is red” on the basis of “the doctrine of common names” might be overcome. The objection is that “the nominalist,” attempting to analyze and by construing the pronouns in these sentences as two different proper names and “red” as a common name, is forced thereby to construe the copula in both sentences as the “is” of identity, and hence this and that (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Antidiodorean logics and the brentano-husserl's conception of time.Vladimir L. Vasyukov - 1993 - Axiomathes 4 (3):373-388.
    In some systems of Legniewskian Ontology were introduced as a toolkit for Husserl's and Meinong's theory of objects. Here such consi- deration is extended to Brentano-Husserl's theory of time. So-called antidiodo- rean logics are used as the foundations of the approach undertaken.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A leśniewskian guide to Husserl's and meinong's jungles.Vladimir L. Vasyukov - 1993 - Axiomathes 4 (1):59-74.
  • Lesniewski and Russell's paradox: Some problems.Rafal Urbaniak - 2008 - History and Philosophy of Logic 29 (2):115-146.
    Sobocinski in his paper on Leśniewski's solution to Russell's paradox (1949b) argued that Leśniewski has succeeded in explaining it away. The general strategy of this alleged explanation is presented. The key element of this attempt is the distinction between the collective (mereological) and the distributive (set-theoretic) understanding of the set. The mereological part of the solution, although correct, is likely to fall short of providing foundations of mathematics. I argue that the remaining part of the solution which suggests a specific (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Busting a Myth about Leśniewski and Definitions.Rafal Urbaniak & K. Severi Hämäri - 2012 - History and Philosophy of Logic 33 (2):159-189.
    A theory of definitions which places the eliminability and conservativeness requirements on definitions is usually called the standard theory. We examine a persistent myth which credits this theory to Leśniewski, a Polish logician. After a brief survey of its origins, we show that the myth is highly dubious. First, no place in Leśniewski's published or unpublished work is known where the standard conditions are discussed. Second, Leśniewski's own logical theories allow for creative definitions. Third, Leśniewski's celebrated ‘rules of definition’ lay (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Embeddings between the elementary ontology with an atom and the monadic second-order predicate logic.Mitio Takano - 1987 - Studia Logica 46 (3):247 - 253.
    Let EOA be the elementary ontology augmented by an additional axiom S (S S), and let LS be the monadic second-order predicate logic. We show that the mapping which was introduced by V. A. Smirnov is an embedding of EOA into LS. We also give an embedding of LS into EOA.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A semantical investigation into leśniewski's axiom of his ontology.Mitio Takano - 1985 - Studia Logica 44 (1):71 - 77.
    A structure A for the language L, which is the first-order language (without equality) whose only nonlogical symbol is the binary predicate symbol , is called a quasi -struoture iff (a) the universe A of A consists of sets and (b) a b is true in A ([p) a = {p } & p b] for every a and b in A, where a(b) is the name of a (b). A quasi -structure A is called an -structure iff (c) {p (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • An essay on resolution logics.Zbigniew Stachniak - 1993 - Studia Logica 52 (2):309 - 322.
    This paper discusses the resolution principle in the context of non-classical logics.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Embedding the elementary ontology of stanisław leśniewski into the monadic second-order calculus of predicates.V. A. Smirnov - 1983 - Studia Logica 42 (2-3):197 - 207.
    LetEO be the elementary ontology of Leniewski formalized as in Iwanu [1], and letLS be the monadic second-order calculus of predicates. In this paper we give an example of a recursive function , defined on the formulas of the language ofEO with values in the set of formulas of the language of LS, such that EO A iff LS (A) for each formulaA.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • “∊” and Common Names.Vito F. Sinisi - 1965 - Philosophy of Science 32 (3):281-286.
    In [6] I tried to show how an objection to “the nominalist's” analysis of (a) “This is red” and (b) “That is red” on the basis of “the doctrine of common names” might be overcome. The objection is that “the nominalist,” attempting to analyze (a) and (b) by construing the pronouns in these sentences as two different proper names and “red” as a common name, is forced thereby to construe the copula in both sentences as the “is” of identity, and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • “∊” and Common Names.Vito F. Sinisi - 1965 - Philosophy of Science 32 (3/4):281 - 286.
    In [6] I tried to show how an objection to “the nominalist's” analysis of “This is red” and “That is red” on the basis of “the doctrine of common names” might be overcome. The objection is that “the nominalist,” attempting to analyze and by construing the pronouns in these sentences as two different proper names and “red” as a common name, is forced thereby to construe the copula in both sentences as the “is” of identity, and hence this and that (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Leśniewského pojetí jmen jako třídových jmen.Zuzana Rybaříková - 2019 - Pro-Fil 20 (2):2-14.
    Stanisław Leśniewski developed a system of logic and foundations of mathematics that considerably differs from Russell and Whitehead’s system. The difference between these two approaches to logic is significant primarily in the case of Leśniewski’s calculus of names, Ontology, and the concept of names that it contains. Russell’s theory of descriptions played a much more important role than Leśniewski’s concept of names in the history of philosophy. In response to that, several researchers aimed to approximate Leśniewski’s concept of names to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A conceptualist interpretation of Lesniewski's ontology.Nino B. Cocchiarella - 2001 - History and Philosophy of Logic 22 (1):29-43.
    A first-order formulation of Leśniewski's ontology is formulated and shown to be interpretable within a free first-order logic of identity extended to include nominal quantification over proper and common-name concepts. The latter theory is then shown to be interpretable in monadic second-order predicate logic, which shows that the first-order part of Leśniewski's ontology is decidable.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Podstawy logiki nazw.Adelina Morawiec - 1961 - Studia Logica 12 (1):145 - 170.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Note critiche.Massimo Libardi & Roberto Poli - 1993 - Axiomathes 4 (1):105-140.
  • Definitions And Contradictions. Russell, Poincaré, And Lesniewski.François Lepage - 2008 - The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication 4.
    This paper is composed of two independent parts. The first is concerned with Russell’s early philosophy of mathematics and his quarrel with Poincaré about the nature of their opposition. I argue that the main divergence between the two philosophers was about the nature of definitions. In the second part, I briefly present Le!niewski’s Ontology and suggest that Le!niewski’s original treatment of definitions in the foundations of mathematics is the natural solution to the problem that divided Russell and Poincaré.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Consistency of lesniewski's mereology.Czesław Lejewski - 1969 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 34 (3):321-328.
  • Accommodating the informal notion of class within the framework of Lesaniewski's Ontology.Czestaw Lejewski - 1985 - Dialectica 39 (3):217-241.
    SummaryInterpreted distributively the sentence‘Indiana is a member of the class of American federal states’means the same as‘Indiana is an American federal state’. In accordance with the collective sense of class expressions the sentence can be understood as implying that Indiana is a part of the country whose capital city is Washington. Neither interpretation appears to accommodate all the intuitions connected with the informal notion of class. A closer accommodation can be achieved, it seems, if class expressions are interpreted as verb‐like (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • An Axiomatisation of a Pure Calculus of Names.Piotr Kulicki - 2012 - Studia Logica 100 (5):921-946.
    A calculus of names is a logical theory describing relations between names. By a pure calculus of names we mean a quantifier-free formulation of such a theory, based on classical propositional calculus. An axiomatisation of a pure calculus of names is presented and its completeness is discussed. It is shown that the axiomatisation is complete in three different ways: with respect to a set theoretical model, with respect to Leśniewski's Ontology and in a sense defined with the use of axiomatic (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Two kinds of quotation mark expressions in formalized languages.Tadeusz Kubiński - 1965 - Studia Logica 17 (1):31 - 51.
  • Nazwy nieostre.Tadeusz Kubiński - 1958 - Studia Logica 7 (1):115 - 179.
  • Vague terms.Tadeusz Kubiński - 1958 - Studia Logica 7 (1):115-179.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • An attempt to bring logic nearer to colloquial language.Tadeusz Kubinski - 1960 - Studia Logica 10 (1):61-75.
  • The difficulty with the well-formedness of ontological statements.Guido Küng - 1983 - Topoi 2 (1):111-119.
    When Russell argued for his ontological convictions, for instance that there are negative facts or that there are universals, he expressed himself in English. But Wittgenstein must have noticed that from the point of view of Russell's ideal language these ontological statements appear to be pseudo-propositions. He believed therefore that what these statements pretend to say, could not really be said but only shown. Carnap discovered a way out of this mutism: what in the material mode of speech of the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Remarks about syllogistic with negative terms.Bogusław Iwanuś - 1969 - Studia Logica 24 (1):131 - 141.
  • On leśniewski's elementary ontology.Bogusław Iwanuś - 1973 - Studia Logica 31 (1):73 - 125.
  • An extension of the traditional logic containing the elementary ontology and the algebra of classes.Bogusław Iwanuś - 1969 - Studia Logica 25 (1):97 - 139.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On Blass Translation for Leśniewski’s Propositional Ontology and Modal Logics.Takao Inoué - 2021 - Studia Logica 110 (1):265-289.
    In this paper, we shall give another proof of the faithfulness of Blass translation of the propositional fragment \ of Leśniewski’s ontology in the modal logic \ by means of Hintikka formula. And we extend the result to von Wright-type deontic logics, i.e., ten Smiley-Hanson systems of monadic deontic logic. As a result of observing the proofs we shall give general theorems on the faithfulness of B-translation with respect to normal modal logics complete to certain sets of well-known accessibility relations (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Sound Interpretation of Leśniewski's Epsilon in Modal Logic KTB.Takao Inoue - 2021 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 50 (4):455-463.
    In this paper, we shall show that the following translation \(I^M\) from the propositional fragment \(\bf L_1\) of Leśniewski's ontology to modal logic \(\bf KTB\) is sound: for any formula \(\phi\) and \(\psi\) of \(\bf L_1\), it is defined as (M1) \(I^M(\phi \vee \psi) = I^M(\phi) \vee I^M(\psi)\), (M2) \(I^M(\neg \phi) = \neg I^M(\phi)\), (M3) \(I^M(\epsilon ab) = \Diamond p_a \supset p_a. \wedge. \Box p_a \supset \Box p_b.\wedge. \Diamond p_b \supset p_a\), where \(p_a\) and \(p_b\) are propositional variables corresponding to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Leśniewski's Systems of Logic and Foundations of Mathematics.Rafal Urbaniak - 2013 - Cham, Switzerland: Springer.
    With material on his early philosophical views, his contributions to set theory and his work on nominalism and higher-order quantification, this book offers a uniquely expansive critical commentary on one of analytical philosophy’s great ...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Rejection in Łukasiewicz's and Słupecki' Sense.Urszula Wybraniec-Skardowska - 2018 - Lvov-Warsaw School. Past and Present.
    The idea of rejection originated by Aristotle. The notion of rejection was introduced into formal logic by Łukasiewicz [20]. He applied it to complete syntactic characterization of deductive systems using an axiomatic method of rejection of propositions [22, 23]. The paper gives not only genesis, but also development and generalization of the notion of rejection. It also emphasizes the methodological approach to biaspectual axiomatic method of characterization of deductive systems as acceptance (asserted) systems and rejection (refutation) systems, introduced by Łukasiewicz (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark