Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The Implicit Affection Between Kantian Judgment and Aristotelian Rhetoric.Joseph Tinguely - 2015 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 48 (1):1-25.
    Recent scholarship on Kant and rhetoric suggests an inclusive relation between affectivity and cognitive judgment, but that position runs counter to a traditional philosophical opposition between sensibility and rationality. A way to overcome this opposition comes into view in the overlap in three significant areas between Kantian judgment and Aristotelian rhetoric. First, each allows that communicative capacities operate within the way a perceptual object or scene appears in the first place. Secondly, each significantly broadens such communicative capacities so as to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kant on community: A reply to Gehrke.Scott R. Stroud - 2006 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 39 (2):157-165.
  • Kant on the Power and Limits of Pathos: Toward a "Critique of Poetic Rhetoric".Samuel Stoner - 2017 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 50 (1):73-95.
    Upon first encountering Immanuel Kant’s 1766 essay Dreams of a Spirit-Seer Elucidated by Dreams of Metaphysics, one is immediately struck by its literary style. Indeed, Dreams constitutes a unique moment in Kant’s literary development—never before had he thrown himself with such fervor into the attempt to express his thoughts in a provocative manner, and never again would he indulge his poetic tendencies with such reckless abandon. Unsurprisingly, then, Kant’s poetic rhetoric in Dreams has long puzzled readers. Immediately following the essay’s (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kant-Bibliographie 2005.Margit Ruffing - 2007 - Kant Studien 98 (4):487-550.
  • Normative Reasoning and Moral Argumentation in Theory and Practice.Ryan Gillespie - 2016 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 49 (1):49-73.
    “Morality is relative to culture” is a descriptive claim; many people in many different cultures have different moral beliefs. When one adopts moral relativism, however, the claim accrues a normative dimension, in that what follows from relativity is the flattening out of rightness, of one moral belief being better than another regardless of culture. But in practice, humans rarely, if ever, actually behave as if certain things or beliefs are not better than others, as evidenced in everything from foreign policy (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Sources of Kant’s Cosmopolitanism: Basedow, Rousseau, and Cosmopolitan Education.Georg Cavallar - 2013 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 33 (4):369-389.
    The goal of this essay is to analyse the influence of Johann Bernhard Basedow and Rousseau on Kant’s cosmopolitanism and concept of cosmopolitan education. It argues that both Basedow and Kant defined cosmopolitan education as non-denominational moral formation or Bildung, encompassing—in different forms—a thin version of moral religion following the core tenets of Christianity. Kant’s encounter with Basedow and the Philanthropinum in Dessau helps to understand the development of Kant’s concept of cosmopolitanism and educational theory ‘in weltbürgerlicher Absicht’. Rousseau’s role (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations