Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Philosophy of information and transhumanism: Explications of philosophical anthropology.O. V. Marchenko & P. V. Kretov - 2019 - Anthropological Measurements of Philosophical Research 16:102-115.
    Purpose. The research is aimed at finding out the grounds, forms and essence of the correlation between the projects of information philosophy and transhumanism from the point of view of the problematics of philosophical anthropology. Attention is focused on the status of the knowing subject and the transformations of the forms of its activity within the specified correlation. Theoretical basis. Insufficient thinking on the issue of the functioning of traditional cognitive models, in particular Kant’s transcendental questioning, which formed the basis (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What are the contributions of the direct perception approach?Carl B. Zuckerman - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):407-408.
  • The computational/representational paradigm as normal science: further support.Steven W. Zucker - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):406-407.
  • Consciousness: Limited but consequential.Timothy D. Wilson - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):701-701.
  • Percepts, intervening variables, and neural mechanisms.Wally Welker - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):405-406.
  • Logical atomism and computation do not refute Gibson.Walter B. Welmer - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):405-405.
  • No conscious or co-conscious?Graham F. Wagstaff - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):700-700.
  • In defense of invariances and higher-order stimuli.K. von Fieandt - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):404-405.
  • Is human information processing conscious?Max Velmans - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):651-69.
    Investigations of the function of consciousness in human information processing have focused mainly on two questions: (1) where does consciousness enter into the information processing sequence and (2) how does conscious processing differ from preconscious and unconscious processing. Input analysis is thought to be initially "preconscious," "pre-attentive," fast, involuntary, and automatic. This is followed by "conscious," "focal-attentive" analysis which is relatively slow, voluntary, and flexible. It is thought that simple, familiar stimuli can be identified preconsciously, but conscious processing is needed (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   346 citations  
  • Consciousness from a first-person perspective.Max Velmans - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):702-726.
    This paper replies to the first 36 commentaries on my target article on “Is human information processing conscious?” (Behavioral and Brain Sciences,1991, pp.651-669). The target article focused largely on experimental studies of how consciousness relates to human information processing, tracing their relation from input through to output, while discussion of the implications of the findings both for cognitive psychology and philosophy of mind was relatively brief. The commentaries reversed this emphasis, and so, correspondingly, did the reply. The sequence of topics (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   131 citations  
  • Attention is necessary for word integration.Geoffrey Underwood - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):698-698.
  • Perception, information, and computation.S. Ullman - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):408-415.
  • Against direct perception.Shimon Ullman - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):333-81.
    Central to contemporary cognitive science is the notion that mental processes involve computations defined over internal representations. This view stands in sharp contrast to the to visual perception and cognition, whose most prominent proponent has been J.J. Gibson. In the direct theory, perception does not involve computations of any sort; it is the result of the direct pickup of available information. The publication of Gibson's recent book (Gibson 1979) offers an opportunity to examine his approach, and, more generally, to contrast (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   174 citations  
  • Clinical artificial intelligence.Virginia Teller & Hartvig Dahl - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (4):549-550.
  • Is PARRY paranoid?David W. Swanson - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (4):548-549.
  • Damn! There goes that ghost again!Keith E. Stanovich - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):696-698.
  • Dissociating consciousness from cognition.David Spiegel - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):695-696.
  • What kind of indirect process is visual perception?Aaron Sloman - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):401-404.
  • The Mind as a Control System.Aaron Sloman - 1993 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 34:69-110.
    This is not a scholarly research paper, but a ‘position paper’ outlining an approach to the study of mind which has been gradually evolving since about 1969 when I first become acquainted with work in Artificial Intelligence through Max Clowes. I shall try to show why it is more fruitful to construe the mind as a control system than as a computational system.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Developing concepts of consciousness.Aaron Sloman - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):694-695.
  • Deep and shallow simulations.Aaron Sloman - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (4):548-548.
  • A lawful first-person psychology involving a causal consciousness: A psychoanalytic solution.Howard Shevrin - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):693-694.
  • Abstract machine theory and direct perception.Robert Shaw & James Todd - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):400-401.
  • Isn't the first-person perspective a bad third-person perspective?W. Schaeken & G. D'Ydewalle - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):692-693.
  • There is more to psychological meaningfulness than computation and representation.Sverker Runeson - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):399-400.
  • Difficulties with a direct theory of perception.Irvin Rock - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):398-399.
  • A limitation of the reflex-arc approach to consciousness.J. Steven Reznick & Philip David Zelazo - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):692-692.
  • Reasons for doubting the existence of even epiphenomenal consciousness.Georges Rey - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):691-692.
  • Evaluation of a model's test.Russell Revlin - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (4):547-548.
  • Psychiatry and computers: An uneasy synthesis.William H. Reid & John F. Riedler - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (4):547-547.
  • Information pickup is the activity of perceiving.Edward S. Reed - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):397-398.
  • Animal-environment mutuality and direct perception.Sandra S. Prindle, Claudia Carello & M. T. Turvey - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):395-397.
  • How wrong is Gibson?K. Prazdny - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):394-395.
  • The dichotomous predicament of contemporary psychology.V. Pinkava - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (4):546-547.
  • Modeling paranoia: The cargo cult metaphor.Keith Oatley - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (4):545-546.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Al and cargo cult science.James Moor - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (4):544-545.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • PARRY and the evaluation of cognitive models.James R. Miller - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (4):543-544.
  • From Computer Metaphor to Computational Modeling: The Evolution of Computationalism.Marcin Miłkowski - 2018 - Minds and Machines 28 (3):515-541.
    In this paper, I argue that computationalism is a progressive research tradition. Its metaphysical assumptions are that nervous systems are computational, and that information processing is necessary for cognition to occur. First, the primary reasons why information processing should explain cognition are reviewed. Then I argue that early formulations of these reasons are outdated. However, by relying on the mechanistic account of physical computation, they can be recast in a compelling way. Next, I contrast two computational models of working memory (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The processing of information is not conscious, but its products often are.George Mandler - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):688-689.
  • Epi-arguments for epiphenomenalism.Bruce Mangan - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):689-690.
  • Testing the components of a computer model.Brendan A. Maher - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (4):543-543.
  • Colby's model for paranoia: It's made well, but what is it?Peter A. Magaro & Harvey G. Shulman - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (4):542-543.
  • Perceptual activity and direct perception.William M. Mace - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):392-393.
  • Consciousness is king of the neuronal processors.William A. MacKay - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):687-688.
  • Are mediating representations the ghosts in the machine?Alan K. Mackworth - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):393-394.
  • Visual perception: the shifting domain of discourse.Geoffrey R. Loftus & Elizabeth F. Loftus - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):391-392.
  • Consciousness: Only introspective hindsight?Dan Lloyd - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):686-687.
  • How smart must you be to be crazy?Robert Lindsay - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (4):541-542.
  • Conscious functions and brain processes.Benjamin Libet - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):685-686.