Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. On the Reconciliation of Anthropocentric and Nonanthropocentric Environmental Ethics.Brian K. Steverson - 1996 - Environmental Values 5 (4):349-361.
    I argue that James Sterba's recent attempt to show that, despite their foundational axiological differences regarding the relative value of humans and members of nonhuman species, anthropocentrists and nonanthropocentrists would accept the exact same principles of environmental justice fails. The failure to reconcile the two positions is a product of an underestimation of the divergence that occurs at the level of general principles and practical policy as a result of the initial value commitments which characterise each position. The upshot of (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Sources of values in the environmental design professions: The case of landscape architecture.Ian Thompson - 2000 - Ethics, Place and Environment 3 (2):203 – 219.
    This paper presents a framework for understanding the value systems inherent in landscape architectural practice. It is based upon a close analytical reading of the academic and professional literature, supported by a series of in-depth interviews with mid- and late-career British landscape architects. The empirical results of these interviews will be presented in a future paper. A tripartite classification of values is suggested, based upon the categories of the aesthetic, the social and the environmental, each of which is internally complex. (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Sources of values in the environmental design professions: The case of landscape architecture.Ian Thompson - 2000 - Philosophy and Geography 3 (2):203-219.
    This paper presents a framework for understanding the value systems inherent in landscape architectural practice. It is based upon a close analytical reading of the academic and professional literature, supported by a series of in‐depth interviews with mid‐ and late‐career British landscape architects. The empirical results of these interviews will be presented in a future paper. A tripartite classification of values is suggested, based upon the categories of the aesthetic, the social and the environmental, each of which is internally complex. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Reconciliation Reaffirmed: A Reply to Steverson.James P. Sterba - 1996 - Environmental Values 5 (4):363 - 368.
    In this reply to Brian Steverson's objections to my reconciliationist argument, I have clarified the requirements that follow from my principles of environmental justice. I have also clarified the notion of intrinsic value that I am endorsing and the grounds on which my claim of greater intrinsic value for humans rests.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Environmental Egalitarianism and 'Who do you Save?' Dilemmas.Mark A. Michael - 1997 - Environmental Values 6 (3):307 - 325.
    Some critics have understood environmental egalitarianism to imply that human and animal lives are generally equal in value, so that killing a human is no more objectionable than killing a dog. This charge should be troubling for anyone with egalitarian sympathies. I argue that one can distinguish two distinct versions of equality, one based on the idea of equal treatment, the other on the idea of equally valuable lives. I look at a lifeboat case where one must choose between saving (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Beyond Human Racism.Robyn Eckersley - 1998 - Environmental Values 7 (2):165-182.
    In 'Non-Anthropocentrism? A Killing Objection', Tony Lynch and David Wells argue that any attempt to develop a non-anthropocentric morality must invariably slide back to either anthropocentrism (either weak or strong) or a highly repugnant misanthropy in cases of direct conflict between the survival needs of humans and nonhuman species. This reply argues that their attempt to expose the flaws in non-anthropocentrism deflects attention away from the crux of the ecocentric critique, which can best be understood if we replace the confusing (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Kenosis, Nature, and Anthropocentrism: A Response to Fulvi.Paolo Diego Bubbio - 2022 - Comparative and Continental Philosophy 14 (3):205-216.
    In this paper I address the issues raised by Daniele Fulvi, by focusing on the alleged anthropocentrism of my approach to kenotic thought. I defend ontological anthropocentrism (as opposed to ethical anthropocentrism), arguing that a qualified ontological anthropocentrism is not only inevitable, but also more appropriate in order to think of nature in the context of kenotic thought. Subsequently, I address the question of the relation between kenosis and truth, and the issue of how kenotic thought could, and should, relate (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Rights & Nature: Approaching Environmental Issues by Way of Human Rights.Andrew T. Brei - 2013 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 26 (2):393-408.
    Due to the significant and often careless human impact on the natural environment, there are serious problems facing the people of today and of future generations. To date, ethical, aesthetic, religious, and economic arguments for the conservation and protection of the natural environment have made relatively little headway. Another approach, one capable of garnering attention and motivating action, would be welcome. There is another approach, one that I will call a rights approach. Speaking generally, this approach is an attempt to (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations