Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The meaning of representation in animal memory.H. L. Roitblat - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):353-372.
    A representation is a remnant of previous experience that allows that experience to affect later behavior. This paper develops a metatheoretical view of representation and applies it to issues concerning representation in animals. To describe a representational system one must specify the following: thedomainor range of situations in the represented world to which the system applies; thecontentor set of features encoded and preserved by the system; thecodeor transformational rules relating features of the representation to the corresponding features of the represented (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   312 citations  
  • Democritus’ Theory of Colour.Kelli Rudolph - 2019 - Rhizomata 7 (2):269-305.
    I argue that Democritus presents a theory of colour in which the predominance of atomic shapes and microstructural arrangements are neces- sary but not sufficient for colour vision. Focusing primarily on Democritus’ basic colours, I analyse his microstructural account, providing a new analysis of the natural and technological underpinnings of his method of explanation. I argue that the notion of predominance allows Democritus to account for both the varia- tion and the repeatable correspondence of colour perception by setting limits on (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Democritus’ Theory of Colour.Kelli Rudolph - 2019 - Rhizomata 7 (2):269-305.
    I argue that Democritus presents a theory of colour in which the predominance of atomic shapes and microstructural arrangements are necessary but not sufficient for colour vision. Focusing primarily on Democritus’ basic colours, I analyse his microstructural account, providing a new analysis of the natural and technological underpinnings of his method of explanation. I argue that the notion of predominance allows Democritus to account for both the variation and the repeatable correspondence of colour perception by setting limits on possible microstructures. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The heuristic value of representation.Thomas R. Zentall - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):393-394.
  • Mind the brain.Martha Wilson - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):393-393.
  • Internal representations and indeterminacy: A skeptical view.William R. Uttal - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):392-393.
  • Parmenides’ Epistemology and the Two Parts of his Poem.Shaul Tor - 2015 - Phronesis 60 (1):3-39.
    _ Source: _Volume 60, Issue 1, pp 3 - 39 This paper pursues a new approach to the problem of the relation between Alētheia and Doxa. It investigates as interrelated matters Parmenides’ impetus for developing and including Doxa, his conception of the mortal epistemic agent in relation both to Doxa’s investigations and to those in Alētheia, and the relation between mortal and divine in his poem. Parmenides, it is argued, maintained that Doxastic cognition is an ineluctable and even appropriate aspect (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Animal versus human minds.H. S. Terrace - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):391-392.
  • In the beginning was the word.J. E. R. Staddon - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):390-391.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Historicism, behaviorism, and the conceptual status of memory representations in animals.Charles P. Shimp - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):389-390.
  • Expectancy: The endogenous source of anticipatory activities, including “pseudoconditioned” responses.Patrick J. Sheafor - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):387-389.
  • Metatheory of animal behavior.Erwin M. Segal - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):386-387.
  • The logic of representation.William W. Rozeboom - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):385-386.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Representations and cognition.H. L. Roitblat - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):394-406.
  • Premature closure of controversial issues concerning animal memory representations.William A. Roberts - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):384-385.
  • Plato’s Theory of Language: the Isomorphism of Kosmos and Logos in the Timaeus.Alexey Pleshkov - 2017 - Problemos 91:128.
    The paper considers Plato’s theory of language through the prism of the Timaeus’ metaphysics. It is argued that the apparent contradictions of Plato’s philosophy of language are the consequence of the two-fold nature of language, and that the metaphysical scheme proposed by Plato in the Timaeus can shed a light on his coherent theory of language. The linguo-metaphysical isomorphism of the Timaeus presupposes that (1) words and material elements have their own meaning and nature respectively; (2) they can be reduced (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the content of representations.R. J. Nelson - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):384-384.
  • Some thoughts on the proper foundations for the study of cognition in animals.Lynn Nadel - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):383-384.
  • A la représentation du temps perdu.John C. Marshall - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):382-383.
  • Echoes of Theophrastus’De sensibusin Books 4 and 1 of the AëtianPlacita.Jaap Mansfeld - 2020 - Rhizomata 7 (2):146-167.
    The hypothesis formulated by Usener and Diels that Theophrastus’ De sensibus is a crucial source of relevant sections of the Placita is insufficiently supported by the evidence. Of the fifteen Placita chapters dealing with sense perception and cognition, only a few are related to the treatise.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Cognitive psychology's representation of behaviorism.A. W. Logue - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):381-382.
  • Memory representations in animals: Some metatheoretical issues.Roy Lachman & Janet L. Lachman - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):380-381.
  • Knowing by likeness in empedocles.Rachana Kamtekar - 2009 - Phronesis 54 (3):215-238.
    Contrary to the Aristotelian interpretation of Empedocles' views about cognition, according to which all cognition, like perception, is due to the compositional likeness between subject and object of cognition, this paper argues that when Empedocles says that we know one thing 'by' another (e.g. earth by earth or love by love), he is characterizing analogical reasoning, an intellectual activity quite different from perception (which is explained by the fit between effluences and pores). The paper also explores the idea that strife (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Principle that ‘Like Perceives Like’ in Theophrastus’De sensibus.Thomas Kjeller Johansen - 2020 - Rhizomata 7 (2):226-248.
    This paper considers Theophrastus’ use in the De sensibus of the principles that like perceives like and that unlike perceives unlike to criticise his predecessors. It is argued that the aporiai that arise from either position serve to motivate the view of perception articulated by Aristotle in the De anima.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Representations as metaphiers.Julian Jaynes - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):379-380.
  • Theophrastus on Plato’s Theory of Vision.Katerina Ierodiakonou - 2020 - Rhizomata 7 (2):249-268.
    In paragraphs 5 and 86 of the De sensibus Theophrastus gives a brief report of Plato’s views on the sense of vision and its object, i. e. colour, based on the Timaeus. Interestingly enough, he presents the Platonic doctrine as a third alternative to the extramission and intromission theories put forward by other ancient philosophers. In this article I examine whether or not Theophrastus’ account is impartial. I argue that at least some of his distortive departures from the Platonic dialogue (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Comparative cognition revisited.Stewart H. Hulse - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):379-379.
  • Some distinctions among representations.M. Gopnik - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):378-379.
  • Representation: A concept that fills no gaps.Robert Epstein - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):377-378.
  • The informational character of representations.Fred Dretske - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):376-377.
  • Memory: A matter of fitness.Juan D. Delius - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):375-376.
  • Behaviorism's new cognitive representations: Paradigm regained.Arthur C. Danto - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):375-375.
  • Empedocles on Sensation, Perception, and Thought.Patricia Curd - 2016 - History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 19 (1):38-57.
    Aristotle claims that Empedocles took perception and knowledge to be the same; Theophrastus follows Aristotle. The paper begins by examining why Aristotle and Theophrastus identify thought/knowing with perception in Empedocles. I maintain that the extant fragments do not support the assertion that Empedocles identifies or conflates sensation with thought or cognition. Indeed, the evidence of the texts shows that Empedocles is careful to distinguish them, and argues that to have genuine understanding one must not be misled into supposing that sense (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Antimisrepresentationalism.A. Charles Catania - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):374-375.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Theophrastus on Perceiving.Victor Caston - 2020 - Rhizomata 7 (2):188-225.
    Many fragments from Theophrastus on perception are preserved by the late Neoplatonist, Priscian of Lydia. After preliminary source criticism concerning how to identify the fragments, I turn to Theophrastus’ discussion of perceiving and perceptual awareness. While he clearly rejects literalism, he also does not embrace “spiritualism”: he argues instead that we receive the defining proportions of perceptible qualities in the sense organ, though in different contraries than in the perceptible (thereby avoiding literalism). If Priscian’s report is faithful, Theophrastus also accepts (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Memory and rules in animal serial learning.E. J. Capaldi - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):373-373.
  • Misrepresenting behaviorism.Marc N. Branch - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):372-373.
  • Theophrastus’De sensibus in A-fragments of Diels-Kranz. Revisiting the Testimonia and their Value.Han Baltussen - 2020 - Rhizomata 7 (2):120-145.
    As a crucial source for Presocratic theories of sense perception, Theophrastus’ De sensibus deserves a closer scrutiny than the placement among A-fragments, as often suggested or instigated. This paper proposes to refine our terminology for labelling the varying quality of reporting within the A-fragments has. It supplements the existing criticism of Diels’ division by analysing neglected features. A reassessment of the assumptions underlying the terms ‘fragment’ and ‘paraphrase’ can contribute to dissolving the sharp distinction between A- and B-fragments in DK. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dyschereia and Aporia: The Formation of a Philosophical Term.Wei Cheng - 2018 - TAPA 148 (1):75-110.
    Plato’s nephew Speusippus has been widely accepted as the historical person behind the mask of the anti-hedonists in Phlb. 42b–44c. This hypothesis is supported by, inter alia, the link between Socrates’ char- acterization of them as δυσχερεῖς and the frequent references of δυσχέρεια as ἀπορία to Speusippus in Aristotle’s Metaphysics MN. This study argues against assigning any privileged status to Speusippus in the assimilation of δυσχέρεια with ἀπορία. Instead, based on a comprehensive survey of how δυσχερ- words were used in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Leibnizin pienet havainnot ja tunteiden muodostuminen.Markku Roinila - 2018 - Havainto.
    Keskityn siihen miten Leibnizilla yksittäiset mielihyvän tai mielipahan tiedostamattomat havainnot voivat kasautua tai tiivistyä ja muodostaa vähitellen tunteita, joista tulemme tietoisiksi.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Persistence of Category Mistakes in Psychology.Per Holth - 2001 - Behavior and Philosophy 29:203 - 219.
    Gilbert Ryle's book The Concept of Mind was published in 1949. According to Ryle, his "destructive purpose" was to show that "a family of radical category mistakes" is the source of the "official doctrine," that is, a "double-life theory," according to which "with the doubtful exception of idiots and infants in arms every human being has both a body and a mind." By numerous examples, Ryle showed quite forcefully how psychology and philosophy at the time were misled into asking the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations