Switch to: References

Citations of:

A reply to my critics

In James Tully (ed.), Meaning and Context: Quentin Skinner and His Critics. Polity Press. pp. 234 (1988)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The Oxford Handbook of Philosophical Methodology.Herman Cappelen, Tamar Gendler & John Hawthorne (eds.) - 2016 - Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
    This is the most comprehensive book ever published on philosophical methodology. A team of thirty-eight of the world's leading philosophers present original essays on various aspects of how philosophy should be and is done. The first part is devoted to broad traditions and approaches to philosophical methodology. The entries in the second part address topics in philosophical methodology, such as intuitions, conceptual analysis, and transcendental arguments. The third part of the book is devoted to essays about the interconnections between philosophy (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The tyranny of the definite article: Some thoughts on the art of intellectual history.Brian Young - 2002 - History of European Ideas 28 (1-2):101-117.
    This essay argues, following an insight of Burckhardt, that the philosophy of history is a ‘centaur’, and that it has a tendency to hinder rather than to encourage the practice of history. It challenges many of the presuppositions of Bevir's study, demonstrating that The Logic of the History of Ideas is not, in any meaningful sense, an historically minded work. The ‘logic’ of the essay looks to the arts, especially literature and music, as providing genuinely illuminating parallels to the discipline (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Introduction: Mare Liberum Revisited (1609-2009).Gustaaf van Nifterik & Janne Nijman - 2009 - Grotiana 30 (1):3-19.
    This introduction gives a rough sketch of the context of Mare liberum's publication and the main arguments Grotius made in this pamphlet. It touches briefly on some of the latest arguments on Mare liberum and provides a survey of the contributions to this Commemmorative Issue. Moreover, it sets the stage for the contributions which elaborate on the fate of Grotian concepts - not so much by historically tracing these ideas over the past 400 years, but by offering an analysis of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Philosophical arguments, historical contexts, and theory of education.Daniel Tröhler - 2007 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 39 (1):10–19.
    This paper argues that many philosophical arguments within the education discourse are too little embedded in their own historical contexts. Starting out from the obvious fact that philosophers of education use sources from the past, the paper asks how we can deal with the arguments that these sources contain. The general attitude within philosophy of education, which views arguments as timeless, is being challenged by the insight that arguments always depend upon their own contexts. For this reason, citing past authors, (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Analytical Philosophy and the Philosophy of Intellectual History: A Critical Comparison and Interpretation.Admir Skodo - 2013 - Journal of the Philosophy of History 7 (2):137-161.
    This article argues that the relationship between analytical philosophy and the philosophy of intellectual history is conceptually uneasy and even antagonistic once the general philosophical viewpoints, and some particular topics, of the two perspectives are drawn out and compared. The article critically compares the philosophies of Quentin Skinner and Mark Bevir with the philosophies of Ludwig Wittgenstein, J.L. Austin, W.V.O. Quine and Donald Davidson. Section I compares the way in which these two perspectives view the task of philosophy. Section II (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Quentin Skinner, contextual method and Machiavelli's understanding of liberty.Nikola Regent - 2022 - History of the Human Sciences 35 (5):108-134.
    The article examines Quentin Skinner's influential interpretation of Machiavelli's views on liberty, and the sharp divergence between his methodological ideas and his actual practice. The paper explores how Skinner's political ideals directed his interpretation against his own methodological precepts, to offer a basis for a ‘revival’ of republican theory. Skinner's reinterpretation of Machiavelli as a theorist of negative liberty is examined, and refuted. The article analyses Skinner's claim about liberty as the key political value for Machiavelli, and demonstrates that liberty (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Quentin Skinner's rhetoric of conceptual change.Kari Palonen - 1997 - History of the Human Sciences 10 (2):61-80.
  • Introduction: Mare Liberum Revisited.Janne Nijman & Gustaaf van Nifterik - 2009 - Grotiana 30 (1):3-19.
    This introduction gives a rough sketch of the context of Mare liberum's publication and the main arguments Grotius made in this pamphlet. It touches briefly on some of the latest arguments on Mare liberum and provides a survey of the contributions to this Commemmorative Issue. Moreover, it sets the stage for the contributions which elaborate on the fate of Grotian concepts - not so much by historically tracing these ideas over the past 400 years, but by offering an analysis of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Crisis discourse and framework transition in Maimonides’ Mishneh Torah.Omer Michaelis - 2020 - Open Philosophy 3 (1):664-680.
    In his works from the past decade, Menachem Fisch offered an analysis of a crucial distinction between two modes of rationalized transformation: an intra-framework transformation and an inter-framework one, the latter entailing a revolutionary shift of the framework itself. In this article, I analyze the attempt to produce such a framework transition in the tradition of Jewish Halakha (i.e., Jewish Law) by one of the key figures in its history, Moses Maimonides (1135–1204), and to explore how this transition was rationalized (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The foundations of Habermas's universal pragmatics.Hudson Meadwell - 1994 - Theory and Society 23 (5):711-727.
  • Contextualist dilemmas: Methodology of the history of political theory in two stages.Petri Koikkalainen - 2011 - History of European Ideas 37 (3):315-324.
    This article traces the development of contextualist methodology in the study of the history of political thought/political theory after WWII. It argues that the so-called ‘Cambridge School’, often regarded as the core of historicist contextualism, arose during the 1950s and 1960s in response to dilemmas that were largely internal to (the history of) political philosophy as it was practiced in Britain in an academic culture dominated by analytic philosophy. This first stage of contextualist theorizing, usually associated with Laslett, Skinner and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Re-Reading the Declaration of Independence as Perlocutionary Performative.Yarran Hominh - 2016 - Res Publica 22 (4):423-444.
    This paper addresses the question of the constitution of ‘the people’. It argues that J.L. Austin’s concept of the ‘perlocutionary’ speech act gives us a framework for understanding the constitutive force of a specific constitutional document: the American Declaration of Independence. It does so through responding to Derrida’s analysis of the Declaration, which itself draws on Austin’s work. Derrida argues that the Declaration’s constitutive force lies in the fact that it cannot be simply understood as either ‘performative’ or ‘constative’, in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Rewriting the past: Retrospective description and its consequences.Adrian Haddock - 2002 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 32 (1):3-24.
    This article seeks to answer the following questions: is Quentin Skinner right to claim that actions in the past should not be described by means of concepts not available at the time those actions occurred? And is Ian Hacking right to claim that such descriptions do not merely describe but actually change the past? The author begins by arguing that it is not clear precisely what Skinner is claiming and shows how, under the pressure of criticism, his methodological strictures collapse (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Ein Blick vorwärts in die Vergangenheit: Ein Fall für den historischen Nominalismus.Menachem Fisch - 1992 - Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 40 (11):1279-1294.
  • “Was he right?” R. G. Collingwood’s Rapprochement between Philosophy and History.Christopher Fear - 2017 - Journal of the Philosophy of History 11 (3):408-424.
  • G. H. Mead: a system in a state of flux.Filipe Carreira da Silva - 2007 - History of the Human Sciences 20 (1):45-65.
    This article offers an original, intellectual portrait of G. H. Mead. My reassessment of Mead’s thinking is founded, in methodological terms, upon a historically minded yet theoretically oriented strategy. Mead’s system of thought is submitted to a historical reconstruction in order to grasp the evolution of his ideas over time, and to a thematic reconstruction organized around three major research areas or pillars: science, social psychology and politics. If one re-examines the entirety of Mead’s published and unpublished writings from the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Conceptual History and the Philosophy of the Later Wittgenstein: A Critique of Quentin Skinner’s Contextualist Method.Anthony Burns - 2011 - Journal of the Philosophy of History 5 (1):54-83.
    Although first published in 1969, the methodological views advanced in Quentin Skinner's “Meaning and Understanding in the History of Ideas” remain relevant today. In his article Skinner suggests that it would be inappropriate to even attempt to write the history of any idea or concept. In support of this view, Skinner advances two arguments, one derived from the philosophy of the later Wittgenstein and the other from that of J. L. Austin.In this paper I focus on the first of these (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The role of contexts in understanding and explanation.Mark Bevir - 2000 - Human Studies 23 (4):395-411.
    In considering the Cambridge School of intellectual history, we should distinguish Skinner's conventionalism from Pocock's contextualism whilst recognising that both of them argue that the study of a text's linguistic context is at least necessary and perhaps sufficient to ensure understanding. This paper suggests that although "study the linguistic context of an utterance" is a valuable heuristic maxim, it is not a prerequisite of understanding that one does so. Hence, we might shift our attention from the role of linguistic contexts (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Mind and method in the history of ideas.Mark Bevir - 1997 - History and Theory 36 (2):167–189.
    J. G. A. Pocock and Quentin Skinner have led a recent onslaught on the alleged "myth of coherence" in the history of ideas. But their criticisms depend on mistaken views of the nature of mind: respectively, a form of social constructionism, and a focus on illocutionary intentions at the expense of beliefs. An investigation of the coherence constraints that do operate on our ascriptions of belief shows historians should adopt a presumption of coherence, concern themselves with coherence, and proceed to (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Philosophy and history in the study of political thought.Jens Bartelson - 2007 - Journal of the Philosophy of History 1 (1):101-124.
    This article analyzes how the relationship between philosophy and history has been conceived within the study of political thought, and how different ways of conceiving this relationship in turn have affected the definition of the subject matter as well as the choice of methods within this field. My main argument is that the ways in which we conceive this relationship is dependent on the assumptions we make about the ontological status of concepts and their meaning. I start by discussing the (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark