Switch to: References

Citations of:

Schopenhauer and Nietzsche

Urbana: University of Illinois Press (1907)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Unity in Strife: Nietzsche, Heraclitus and Schopenhauer.James Pearson - 2018 - In James S. Pearson & Herman Siemens (eds.), Conflict and Contest in Nietzsche's Philosophy. New York, NY, USA: Bloomsbury. pp. 44–69.
  • A Dynamic Interpretation of Nietzsche’s “The Greatest Weight”.Robin Small - 2020 - Nietzsche Studien (1973) 49 (1):97-124.
    GS 341 is one of the most familiar of Nietzsche’s writings. This article proposes a new reading that stands in contrast with most English-language Nietzsche scholarship. The text presents a communication and its reception. A ‘demon’ makes an announcement, and a hearer responds in one way or another. But there is also another narrative altogether, whose conceptual vocabulary comes from a dynamic world-view. In this an interaction of forces leads to a new situation. If the hearer is not crushed by (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Knowledge and Selflessness: Schopenhauer and the Paradox of Reflection.Bernard Reginster - 2008 - European Journal of Philosophy 16 (2):251-272.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Simmel's four components of historical science.Richard Owsley & Gary Backhaus - 2003 - Human Studies 26 (2):209-222.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Vitalism as Pathos.Thomas Osborne - 2016 - Biosemiotics 9 (2):185-205.
    This paper addresses the remarkable longevity of the idea of vitalism in the biological sciences and beyond. If there is to be a renewed vitalism today, however, we need to ask – on what kind of original conception of life should it be based? This paper argues that recent invocations of a generalized, processual variety of vitalism in the social sciences and humanities above all, however exciting in their scope, miss much of the basic originality – and interest – of (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The theme of civilization and its discontents in Durkheim's division of labor: Philosophical assumptions and practical consequences.Stjepan G. Meštrovi - 1989 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 19 (4):443–456.
  • Animal faith, puritanism, and the Schutz-Gurwitsch debate: A commentary. [REVIEW]Stanford M. Lyman - 1991 - Human Studies 14 (2-3):199 - 206.
  • Pluralization and Recognition: On the Self-Misunderstanding of Postmodern Social Theorists.Axel Honneth - 1992 - Thesis Eleven 31 (1):24-33.
  • Striving as Suffering: Schopenhauer’s A Priori Argument for Pessimism.Patrick Hassan - 2021 - Philosophia 49 (4):1487-1505.
    This paper aims to clarify Schopenhauer’s a priori argument for pessimism and, to an extent, rescue it from standard objections in secondary literature. I argue that if we separate out the various strands of Schopenhauer’s pessimism, we hit upon problems and counterexamples stemming from psychology. For example, instances where striving does not appear to equate to suffering, which puts pressure on the Schopenhauerian claim that human life, qua instantiation of the will, is painful. Schopenhauer’s sensitivity to the complexities of human (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Nietzsche and Amor Fati.Béatrice Han-Pile - 2011 - European Journal of Philosophy 19 (2):224-261.
    Abstract: This paper identifies two central paradoxes threatening the notion of amor fati [love of fate]: it requires us to love a potentially repellent object (as fate entails significant negativity for us) and this, in the knowledge that our love will not modify our fate. Thus such love may seem impossible or pointless. I analyse the distinction between two different sorts of love (eros and agape) and the type of valuation they involve (in the first case, the object is loved (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Back to truth: Knowledge and pleasure in the aesthetics of Schopenhauer.Paul Guyer - 2008 - European Journal of Philosophy 16 (2):164-178.
  • Axiological and normative dimensions in Georg Simmel’s philosophy and sociology: a dialectical interpretation.Spiros Gangas - 2004 - History of the Human Sciences 17 (4):17-44.
    In this article I consider the normative and axiological dimension of Simmel’s thought. Building on previous interpretations, I argue that although Simmel cannot be interpreted as a systematic normative theorist, the issue of values and the normative standpoint can nevertheless be traced in various aspects of his multifarious work. This interpretive turn attempts to link Simmel’s obscure theory of value with his epistemological relationism. Relationism may offer a counterweight to Simmel’s value-pluralism, since it points to normative elements (e.g. internal teleology, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Nietzsche’s Übermensch as a Metaphor for Education.Peter Fitzsimons - 2007 - Paideusis: Journal of the Canadian Philosophy of Education Society 16 (1):5-15.
    Rather than appealing to universal truth or morality based on the power of reason, Nietzsche’s impassioned plea for resuscitating the embodied self as a source of ethics provides a new perspective on educational philosophy. Within the concept of Will to Power, he offers the notion of the Übermensch as a model for overcoming the social limitations of Christian morality and the dictates of fashion. In a formative state, ‘untimely men’ (and here, read ‘Nietzsche’) stand outside the homogenising influence of the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Schopenhauer’s Pessimism.Jordi Fernández - 2006 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 73 (3):646–664.
    My purpose in this essay is to clarify and evaluate Arthur Schopenhauer's grounds for the view that happiness is impossible. I shall distinguish two of his arguments for that view and argue that both of them are unsound. Both arguments involve premises grounded on a problematic view, namely, that desires have no objects. What makes this view problematic is that, in each of the two arguments, it conflicts with Schopenhauer's grounds for other premises in the argument. I shall then propose (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Schopenhauer’s Pessimism.Jordi Fernández - 2006 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 73 (3):646-664.
    My purpose in this essay is to clarify and evaluate Arthur Schopenhauer's grounds for the view that happiness is impossible. I shall distinguish two of his arguments for that view and argue that both of them are unsound. Both arguments involve premises grounded on a problematic view, namely, that desires have no objects. What makes this view problematic is that, in each of the two arguments, it conflicts with Schopenhauer's grounds for other premises in the argument. I shall then propose (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The pessimistic spirit.Joshua Foa Dienstag - 1999 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 25 (1):71-95.
    Pessimism today is poorly understood. Indeed, such is the disdain that pessimism engenders, that it often has difficulty being taken seriously as a theoretical position. Yet pessimism, which is distinct from skepticism and nihilism, has much to offer those who have discarded the Enlightenment's expectation of progress. Through an examination of Rousseau, Schopenhauer and Unamuno, this paper traces out some of the common themes of pessimistic thought. Pessimism, it is argued, is con-cerned with the burden of time and with the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Sufrimiento y pesimismo en Schopenhauer.Jordi Cabos Teixido - 2015 - Anales Del Seminario de Historia de la Filosofía 32 (1).
  • Schopenhauer and the malaise of an age.Jordi Cabos - 2016 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 42 (1):93-113.
    Although suffering in Schopenhauer’s works may be explained by how the will to life is objectified in the world, a more precise inquiry leads us to elucidate the significance of this experience in his writings. This article claims in the first place that suffering in this author’s works is triggered by multiple sources and takes various forms. In fact, and this is the article’s second claim, these sources coincide with some later scholars’ characterizations of modern suffering. The main aim is (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The standard interpretation of Schopenhauer's compensation argument for pessimism: A nonstandard variant.David Bather Woods - 2021 - European Journal of Philosophy 30 (3):961-976.
    According to Schopenhauer’s compensation argument for pessimism, the non-existence of the world is preferable to its existence because no goods can ever compensate for the mere existence of evil. Standard interpretations take this argument to be based on Schopenhauer’s thesis that all goods are merely the negation of evils, from which they assume it follows that the apparent goods in life are in fact empty and without value. This article develops a non-standard variant of the standard interpretation, which accepts the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Simmel on Acceleration, Boredom, and Extreme Aesthesia.Kevin Aho - 2007 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 37 (4):447-462.
    By focusing on the unique velocity and over-stimulation of metropolitan life, Georg Simmel pioneered an interpretation of cultural boredom that has had a significant impact on contemporary social theory by viewing it through the modern experience of time-pressure and social acceleration. This paper explores Simmel's account of boredom by showing how--in the frenzy of modern life--it has become increasingly difficult to qualitatively distinguish which choices and commitments actually matter to us. Furthermore, this emotional indifference invariably pushes us towards more excessive (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Schopenhauer’s pessimism.David Woods - 2014 - Dissertation, University of Southampton
    In this thesis I offer an interpretation of Arthur Schopenhauer’s pessimism. I argue against interpreting Schopenhauer’s pessimism as if it were merely a matter of temperament, and I resist the urge to find a single standard argument for pessimism in Schopenhauer’s work. Instead, I treat Schopenhauer’s pessimism as inherently variegated, composed of several distinct but interrelated pessimistic positions, each of which is supported by its own argument. I begin by examining Schopenhauer’s famous argument that willing necessitates suffering, which I defend (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations