Switch to: References

Citations of:

The Mind-Body Problem

In Ernest Lepore (ed.), John Searle and His Critics. Cambridge: Blackwell. pp. 141--46 (1991)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. John R. Searle: Consciousness and Language. [REVIEW]Josefa Torobio - 2003 - Philosophy of Science 70 (4):846-849.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Towards a sensible bifurcationism.Jessica Pepp - 2021 - Theoria 88 (2):348-364.
    Theoria, Volume 88, Issue 2, Page 348-364, April 2022.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Self-in-a-Vat: On John Searle's Ontology of Reasons for Acting.Kaufmann Laurence - 2005 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 35 (4):447-479.
    John Searle has recently developed a theory of reasons for acting that intends to rescue the freedom of the will, endangered by causal determinism, whether physical or psychological. To achieve this purpose, Searle postulates a series of “gaps” that are supposed toendowthe self with free will. Reviewing key steps in Searle's argument, this article shows that such an undertaking cannot be successfully completed because of its solipsist premises. The author argues that reasons for acting do not have a subjective, I-ontology (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Paraphrase and the Symmetry Objection.John A. Keller - 2017 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 95 (2):365-378.
    There is a puzzle about the use of paraphrase in philosophy, presented most famously in Alston's [1958] ‘Ontological Commitments’, but found throughout the literature. The puzzle arises from the fact that a symmetry required for a paraphrase to be successful seems to necessitate a symmetry sufficient for a paraphrase to fail, since any two expressions that stand in the means the same as relation must also stand in the has the same commitments as relation. I show that, while this problem (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Self-in-a-vat: On John Searle's ontology of reasons for acting.Laurence Kaufmann - 2005 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 35 (4):447-479.
    John Searle has recently developed a theory of reasons for acting that intends to rescue the freedom of the will, endangered by causal determinism, whether physical or psychological. To achieve this purpose, Searle postulates a series of "gaps" that are supposed toendowthe self with free will. Reviewing key steps in Searle's argument, this article shows that such an undertaking cannot be successfully completed because of its solipsist premises. The author argues that reasons for acting do not have a subjective, I-ontology (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Book ReviewMiklós Rédei and Michael Stölzner , John von Neumann and the Foundations of Physics. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers , ix + 371 pp., $119.00. [REVIEW]Michael Dickson - 2003 - Philosophy of Science 70 (4):855-859.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • “Counting As” a Bridge Principle: Against Searle Against Social-Scientific Laws.William Butchard & Robert D’Amico - 2011 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 41 (4):455-469.
    John Searle’s argument that social-scientific laws are impossible depends on a special open-ended feature of social kinds. We demonstrate that under a noncontentious understanding of bridging principles the so-called "counts-as" relation, found in the expression "X counts as Y in (context) C," provides a bridging principle for social kinds. If we are correct, not only are social-scientific laws possible, but the "counts as" relation might provide a more perspicuous formulation for candidate bridge principles.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Stathis Psillos: Causation and Explanation. [REVIEW]Ingo Brigandt - 2003 - Philosophy of Science 70 (4):844-846.