Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Consciousness is Underived Intentionality.David Bourget - 2010 - Noûs 44 (1):32 - 58.
    Representationalists argue that phenomenal states are intentional states of a special kind. This paper offers an account of the kind of intentional state phenomenal states are: I argue that they are underived intentional states. This account of phenomenal states is equivalent to two theses: first, all possible phenomenal states are underived intentional states; second, all possible underived intentional states are phenomenal states. I clarify these claims and argue for each of them. I also address objections which touch on a range (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • A case of different intentions concerning intentionality.W. Tom Bourbon - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (4):755.
  • Philosophic sur ordinateur ou intelligence artificielle.Gilbert Boss & Maryvonne Longeart - 1993 - Dialogue 32 (2):271-.
    L'informatique se définissant comme le traitement rationnel de l'information par machine automatique et l'intelligence se caractérisant par une même capacité de traitement rationnel, il était inévitable que l'on songe à associer l'intelligence au traitement automatique de l'information. C'est ce qu'a fait John McCarthy en forgeant le terme d'intelligence artificielle. Par «intelligence artificielle» on peut vouloir exprimer l'ambition de1. Recréer, transformer ou développer l'intelligence artificiellement2. Simuler l'intelligence en la reconstituant dans des modéles imitant certains aspects de notre intelligence dite naturelle.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Quantity of experience: brain-duplication and degrees of consciousness. [REVIEW]Nick Bostrom - 2006 - Minds and Machines 16 (2):185-200.
    If a brain is duplicated so that there are two brains in identical states, are there then two numerically distinct phenomenal experiences or only one? There are two, I argue, and given computationalism, this has implications for what it is to implement a computation. I then consider what happens when a computation is implemented in a system that either uses unreliable components or possesses varying degrees of parallelism. I show that in some of these cases there can be, in a (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Non-Stupidity Condition and Pragmatics in Artificial Intelligence.Bojan Borstner & Niko Šetar - 2022 - Croatian Journal of Philosophy 22 (64):101-121.
    Symbol Grounding Problem is commonly considered one of the central challenges in the philosophy of artificial intelligence as its resolution is deemed necessary for bridging the gap between simple data processing and understanding of meaning and language. SGP has been addressed on numerous occasions with varying results, all resolution attempts having been severely, but for the most part justifiably, restricted by the Zero Semantic Commitment Condition. A further condition that demands explanatory power in terms of machine-to-human communication is the Non-Stupidity (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On “seeing” the truth of the Gödel sentence.George Boolos - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):655-656.
  • Determining what is perceived.Radu J. Bogdan - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):66-67.
  • The Philosophy of Cognitive Science.Margaret A. Boden - 2001 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 48:209-226.
    If the Trade Descriptions Act were applied to academic labels, cognitive scientists would be in trouble. For what they do is much wider than the name suggests—and wider, too, than most philosophers assume. They give you more for your money than you may have expected.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Précis of The creative mind: Myths and mechanisms.Margaret A. Boden - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):519-531.
    What is creativity? One new idea may be creative, whereas another is merely new: What's the difference? And how is creativity possible? These questions about human creativity can be answered, at least in outline, using computational concepts. There are two broad types of creativity, improbabilist and impossibilist. Improbabilist creativity involves novel combinations of familiar ideas. A deeper type involves METCS: the mapping, exploration, and transformation of conceptual spaces. It is impossibilist, in that ideas may be generated which – with respect (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Modelling creativity: reply to reviewers.Margaret A. Boden - 1995 - Artificial Intelligence 79 (1):161-182.
  • Life and mind.Margaret A. Boden - 2009 - Minds and Machines 19 (4):453-463.
    It’s sometimes said, and even more often assumed, that life is necessary for mind. If so, and if A-Life promises to throw light on the nature of life as such, then A-Life is in principle highly relevant to the philosophy of mind and cognitive science. However, very few philosophers have attempted to argue for the relation between life and mind. It’s usually taken for granted. Even those (mostly in the Continental tradition, including some with a following in A-Life) who have (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Is metabolism necessary?M. A. Boden - 1999 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 50 (2):231-248.
    Metabolism is a criterion of life. Three senses are distinguished. The weakest allows strong A-Life: virtual creatures having physical existence in computer electronics, but not bodies, are classes as 'alive'. The second excludes strong A-Life but allows that some non-biochemical A-Life robots could be classed as alive. The third, which stresses the body's self-production by energy budgeting and self-equilibrating energy exchanges of some (necessary) complexity, excludes both strong A-Life and living non-biochemical robots.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Creativity: A framework for research.Margaret A. Boden - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):558-570.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Quantum cognition and bounded rationality.Reinhard Blutner & Peter Beim Graben - 2016 - Synthese 193 (10).
    We consider several puzzles of bounded rationality. These include the Allais- and Ellsberg paradox, the disjunction effect, and related puzzles. We argue that the present account of quantum cognition—taking quantum probabilities rather than classical probabilities—can give a more systematic description of these puzzles than the alternate treatments in the traditional frameworks of bounded rationality. Unfortunately, the quantum probabilistic treatment does not always provide a deeper understanding and a true explanation of these puzzles. One reason is that quantum approaches introduce additional (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Consciousness and accessibility.Ned Block - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):596-598.
    This is my first publication of the distinction between phenomenal consciousness and access consciousness, though not using quite those terms. It ends with this: "The upshot is this: If Searle is using the access sense of "consciousness," his argument doesn't get to first base. If, as is more likely, he intends the what-it-is-like sense, his argument depends on assumptions about issues that the cognitivist is bound to regard as deeply unsettled empirical questions." Searle replies: "He refers to what he calls (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   125 citations  
  • Searle’s Wall.James Blackmon - 2013 - Erkenntnis 78 (1):109-117.
    In addition to his famous Chinese Room argument, John Searle has posed a more radical problem for views on which minds can be understood as programs. Even his wall, he claims, implements the WordStar program according to the standard definition of implementation because there is some ‘‘pattern of molecule movements’’ that is isomorphic to the formal structure of WordStar. Program implementation, Searle charges, is merely observer-relative and thus not an intrinsic feature of the world. I argue, first, that analogous charges (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Does the nervous system use equilibrium-point control to guide single and multiple joint movements?E. Bizzi, N. Hogan, F. A. Mussa-Ivaldi & S. Giszter - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (4):603-613.
  • Could the stream of consciousness flow through the brain?Thomas Bittner - 2004 - Philosophia 31 (3-4):449-473.
  • All Watched over by Machines of Silent Grace?John Mark Bishop - 2011 - Philosophy and Technology 24 (3):359-362.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • All Watched over by Machines of Silent Grace?Mark Bishop - 2011 - Philosophy and Technology 24 (3):359-362.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Artificial Intelligence Is Stupid and Causal Reasoning Will Not Fix It.J. Mark Bishop - 2021 - Frontiers in Psychology 11.
    Artificial Neural Networks have reached “grandmaster” and even “super-human” performance across a variety of games, from those involving perfect information, such as Go, to those involving imperfect information, such as “Starcraft”. Such technological developments from artificial intelligence (AI) labs have ushered concomitant applications across the world of business, where an “AI” brand-tag is quickly becoming ubiquitous. A corollary of such widespread commercial deployment is that when AI gets things wrong—an autonomous vehicle crashes, a chatbot exhibits “racist” behavior, automated credit-scoring processes (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Unified cognitive theory: You can't get there from here.Derek Bickerton - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):437-438.
  • Putting cognitive carts before linguistic horses.Derek Bickerton - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):749-750.
  • Kan datamaskiner tenke?Einar Duenger Bøhn - 2023 - Norsk Filosofisk Tidsskrift 58 (2-3):95-105.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Internal events as behavior, not causes.Daniel J. Bernstein - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):55-56.
  • Exclusion Criteria in Experimental Philosophy.Carsten Bergenholtz, Jacob Busch & Sara Kier Praëm - 2019 - Erkenntnis 86 (6):1531-1545.
    When experimental philosophers carry out studies on thought experiments, some participants are excluded based on certain exclusion criteria, mirroring standard social science vignette methodology. This involves excluding people that do not pay attention or who miscomprehend the scenario presented in thought experiments. However, experimental philosophy studies sometimes exclude an alarmingly high number of participants. We argue that this threatens the external and internal validity of the conclusions being drawn and we show how a simple visualization of thought experiments can reduce (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • An Attitude Towards an Artificial Soul? Responses to the “Nazi Chatbot”.Ondřej Beran - 2017 - Philosophical Investigations 41 (1):42-69.
    The article discusses the case of Microsoft's Twitter chatbot Tay that “turned into a Nazi” after less than 24 hours from its release on the Internet. The first section presents a brief recapitulation of Alan Turing's proposal for a test for artificial intelligence and the way it influenced subsequent discussions in the philosophy of mind. In the second section, I offer a few arguments appealing for caution regarding the identification of an accomplished chatbot as a thinking being. These are motivated (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Downward Path to Epistemic Informational Structural Realism.Majid Davoody Beni - 2018 - Acta Analytica 33 (2):181-197.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Method in the Service of Progress.John Bengson, Terence Cuneo & Russ Shafer-Landau - 2019 - Analytic Philosophy 60 (3):179-205.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Behaviorism and psychologism: Why Block’s argument against behaviorism is unsound.Hanoch Ben-Yami - 2005 - Philosophical Psychology 18 (2):179-186.
    Ned Block. Psychologism and behaviorism. Philosophical Review, 90, 5-43.) argued that a behaviorist conception of intelligence is mistaken, and that the nature of an agent's internal processes is relevant for determining whether the agent has intelligence. He did that by describing a machine which lacks intelligence, yet can answer questions put to it as an intelligent person would. The nature of his machine's internal processes, he concluded, is relevant for determining that it lacks intelligence. I argue against Block that it (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • A note on the chinese room.Hanoch Ben-Yami - 1993 - Synthese 95 (2):169-72.
    Searle's Chinese Room was supposed to prove that computers can't understand: the man in the room, following, like a computer, syntactical rules alone, though indistinguishable from a genuine Chinese speaker, doesn't understand a word. But such a room is impossible: the man won't be able to respond correctly to questions like What is the time?, even though such an ability is indispensable for a genuine Chinese speaker. Several ways to provide the room with the required ability are considered, and it (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A critique of the inferential paradigm in perception.Aaron Ben-Zeev - 1987 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 17 (3):243–263.
  • Two constructive themes.Richard K. Belew - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):25-26.
  • Basic questions of the philosophy of artificial intelligence.Evgeniya Konstantinovna Belikova - forthcoming - Philosophy and Culture (Russian Journal).
    The object of the study is a special branch of scientific knowledge, formed at the intersection of interests of various humanitarian disciplines – the philosophy of artificial intelligence; the subject of the study is the problems it considers. The author identifies the main traditional questions that the philosophy of artificial intelligence tried to answer earlier. Such questions in the earlier stages of the development of science were concentrated around the possibility of artificial intelligence to become aware of itself, learn to (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Goal-Directed Systems and the Good.Mark Bedau - 1992 - The Monist 75 (1):34-51.
    We can readily identify goal-directed systems and distinguish them from non-goal-directed systems. A woodpecker hunting for grubs is the first, a pendulum returning to rest is the second. But what is it to be a goal-directed system? Perhaps the dominant answer to this question, inspired by systems theories such as cybernetics, is that goal-directed systems are distinguished by their tendency to seek, aim at, or maintain some more-or-less easily identifiable goal. Cybernetics and the like would hold that physical systems subject (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • The case for connectionism.William Bechtel - 1993 - Philosophical Studies 71 (2):119-54.
  • Sprachverstehende maschinenLanguage understanding machines.Ansgar Beckermann - 1988 - Erkenntnis 28 (1):65-85.
    In this paper the author tries to disentangle some of the problems tied up in John Searle's famous Chinese-room-argument. In a first step to answer the question what it would be for a system to have not only syntax, but also semantics the author gives a brief account of the functioning of the language understanding systems (LUS) so far developed in the framework of AI research thereby making clear that systems like Winograd's SHRDLU are indeed doing little more than mere (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Realism, instrumentalism, and the intentional stance.William Bechtel - 1985 - Cognitive Science 9 (4):265-92.
  • Responsibility and Decision Making in the Era of Neural Networks.William Bechtel - 1996 - Social Philosophy and Policy 13 (2):267.
    Many of the mathematicians and scientists who guided the development of digital computers in the late 1940s, such as Alan Turing and John von Neumann, saw these new devices not just as tools for calculation but as devices that might employ the same principles as are exhibited in rational human thought. Thus, a subfield of what came to be called computer science assumed the label artificial intelligence. The idea of building artificial systems which could exhibit intelligent behavior comparable to that (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Decomposing intentionality: Perspectives on intentionality drawn from language research with two species of chimpanzees. [REVIEW]William Bechtel - 1993 - Biology and Philosophy 8 (1):1-32.
    In philosophy the term intentionality refers to the feature possessed by mental states of beingabout things others than themselves. A serious question has been how to explain the intentionality of mental states. This paper starts with linguistic representations, and explores how an organism might use linguistic symbols to represent other things. Two research projects of Sue Savage-Rumbaugh, one explicity teaching twopan troglodytes to use lexigrams intentionally, and the other exploring the ability of several members ofpan paniscus to learn lexigram use (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Currents in connectionism.William Bechtel - 1993 - Minds and Machines 3 (2):125-153.
    This paper reviews four significant advances on the feedforward architecture that has dominated discussions of connectionism. The first involves introducing modularity into networks by employing procedures whereby different networks learn to perform different components of a task, and a Gating Network determines which network is best equiped to respond to a given input. The second consists in the use of recurrent inputs whereby information from a previous cycle of processing is made available on later cycles. The third development involves developing (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Connectionism and interlevel relations.William Bechtel - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):24-25.
  • Connectionism and the philosophy of mind: An overview.William Bechtel - 1988 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 26 (S1):17-41.
  • Connectionism and the philosophy of mind: An overview.William Bechtel - 1991 - In Terence E. Horgan & John L. Tienson (eds.), Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 30--59.
  • Constructing a Philosophy of Science of Cognitive Science.William Bechtel - 2009 - Topics in Cognitive Science 1 (3):548-569.
    Philosophy of science is positioned to make distinctive contributions to cognitive science by providing perspective on its conceptual foundations and by advancing normative recommendations. The philosophy of science I embrace is naturalistic in that it is grounded in the study of actual science. Focusing on explanation, I describe the recent development of a mechanistic philosophy of science from which I draw three normative consequences for cognitive science. First, insofar as cognitive mechanisms are information-processing mechanisms, cognitive science needs an account of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Constructing a Philosophy of Science of Cognitive Science.William Bechtel - 2009 - Topics in Cognitive Science 1 (3):548-569.
    Philosophy of science is positioned to make distinctive contributions to cognitive science by providing perspective on its conceptual foundations and by advancing normative recommendations. The philosophy of science I embrace is naturalistic in that it is grounded in the study of actual science. Focusing on explanation, I describe the recent development of a mechanistic philosophy of science from which I draw three normative consequences for cognitive science. First, insofar as cognitive mechanisms are information‐processing mechanisms, cognitive science needs an account of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Bedeutungsverstehen als Kennzeichen des Mentalen.Ansgar Beckermann - 1989 - Zeitschrift Für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 20 (1):132-145.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Bedeutungsverstehen AlS kennzeichen Des mentalen.Ansgar Beckermann - 1989 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 20 (1):132-145.
    In his paper "Machines and the Mental" Fred Dretske claims that there is a difference on principle between men on the one and animals and machines on the other side which arises from the fact that men are able to respond to the meaning of symbols whereas animals and machines can only respond to the symbols that have the meaning. In this paper it is argued that this claim does not bear closer scrutiny. Mainly for two reasons: 1. The mere (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Artificial lives, analogies and symbolic thought: an anthropological insight on robots and AI.Joffrey Becker - 2023 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 99 (C):89-96.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On philosophical idling: the ordinary language philosophy critique of the philosophical method of cases.Avner Baz - 2023 - Synthese 201 (3):1-20.
    I start with some of the early challenges to the widely-employed philosophical method of cases—the very challenges that originally prompted the new movement of experimental philosophy—and with some fundamental questions about the method that are yet to have been given satisfying answers. I then propose that what has allowed both ‘armchair’ and ‘experimental’ participants in the ongoing debates concerning the method to ignore or repress those early challenges—and in particular Robert Cummins’s ‘calibration objection’—and to discount fundamental disagreements about those questions, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark