Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. معنای زندگی، عاشقانه‌ترین جهان ممکن و اختفای الهی.محمدجواد الهی اصل & عباس یزدانی - 2022 - پژوهشنامه فلسفه دین 19 (2):201-220.
    شلنبرگ برای اولین بار در سال 1993 استدلالی با عنوان «اختفای الهی» را علیه خداباوری ارائه کرد. از آن زمان تا کنون استدلال او در کانون نقد و دفاع قرار داشته است. در این نوشتار، که با رویکرد تحلیلی-انتقادی انجام می‌پذیرد، ضمن تقریر استدلال شلنبرگ، افزون بر مهم‌ترین نقدهای مطرح‌شده بر استدلال او، دو نقد متفاوت دیگر بر این استدلال مطرح می‌شود. یکی از این نقدها از طریق معنای زندگی است. شلنبرگ در رابطه با مزیت ارتباط عاشقانه با خداوند معتقد (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Can God Satisfice?Klass Kraay - 2013 - American Philosophical Quarterly 50 (4):399-410.
    Three very prominent arguments for atheism are (1) the argument from sub-optimality, (2) the problem of no best world, and (3) the evidential argument from gratuitous evil. To date, it has not sufficiently been appreciated that several important criticisms of these arguments have all relied on a shared strategy. Although the details vary, the core of this strategy is to concede that God either cannot or need not achieve the best outcome in the relevant choice situation, but to insist that (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • The problem of evil: unseen animal suffering.Daniel Molto - 2021 - Religious Studies 57 (2):353-371.
    On my view, every bone, every fossil, and every putrid whiff of carrion that one smells on a hike in the country is just as good evidence for a divine intervention as it is for the suffering of an animal.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hume, Causation and Two Arguments Concerning God.Jason Megill - 2014 - European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 6 (2):169--177.
    In Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, Hume (1779/1993) appeals to his account of causation (among other things) to undermine certain arguments for the existence of God. If 'anything can cause anything', as Hume claims, then the Principle of Causal Adequacy is false; and if the Principle of Causal Adequacy is false, then any argument for God's existence that relies on that principle fails. Of course, Hume's critique has been influential. But Hume's account of causation undermines the argument from evil at least (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Evil and the many universes response.Jason Megill - 2011 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 70 (2):127-138.
    I formulate and defend a version of the many universes (or multiverse) reply to the atheistic argument from evil. Specifically, I argue that (i) if we know that any argument from evil (be it a logical or evidential argument) is sound, then we know that God would be (or at least probably would be) unjustified in actualizing our universe. I then argue that (ii) there might be a multiverse and (iii) if so, then we do not know that God would (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Theism, Possible Worlds, and the Multiverse.Klaas J. Kraay - 2010 - Philosophical Studies 147 (3):355 - 368.
    God is traditionally taken to be a perfect being, and the creator and sustainer of all that is. So, if theism is true, what sort of world should we expect? To answer this question, we need an account of the array of possible worlds from which God is said to choose. It seems that either there is (a) exactly one best possible world; or (b) more than one unsurpassable world; or (c) an infinite hierarchy of increasingly better worlds. Influential arguments (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Creation, Actualization and God's Choice Among Possible Worlds.Klaas J. Kraay - 2008 - Philosophy Compass 3 (4):854-872.
    God is traditionally understood to be a perfect being who is the creator and sustainer of all that is. God's creative and sustaining activity is often thought to involve choosing a possible world for actualization. It is generally said that either there is (a) exactly one best of all possible worlds, or there are (b) infinitely many increasingly better worlds, or else there are (c) infinitely many unsurpassable worlds within God's power to actualize. On each view, critics have offered arguments (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Ability-based objections to no-best-world arguments.Brian Kierland & Philip Swenson - 2013 - Philosophical Studies 164 (3):669-683.
    In the space of possible worlds, there might be a best possible world (a uniquely best world or a world tied for best with some other worlds). Or, instead, for every possible world, there might be a better possible world. Suppose that the latter is true, i.e., that there is no best world. Many have thought that there is then an argument against the existence of God, i.e., the existence of an omnipotent, omniscient and morally perfect being; we will call (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Reflections on deliberative coherence.Leigh B. Kelley - 1988 - Synthese 76 (1):83 - 121.
    This paper treats two problem cases in decision theory, the Newcomb problem and Reed Richter''s Button III. Although I argue that, contrary to Richter, the latter case does not constitute a genuine counterexample to a standard general proposition of (causal) decision theory, I agree with and undertake to amplify his solution to the decision problem in Button III. I then apply the conclusions and distinctions in the foregoing treatment of Button III to the Newcomb problem and argue that a familiar (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the Argument from Divine Arbitrariness.Peter Forrest - 2012 - Sophia 51 (3):341-349.
    William Rowe in his Can God be Free? argues that God, if there is a God, necessarily chooses the best. Combined with the premise that there is no best act of creation, this provides an a priori argument for atheism. Rowe assumes that necessarily God is a ‘morally unsurpassable’ being, and it is for that reason that God chooses the best. In this article I drop that assumption and I consider a successor to Rowe ’s argument, the Argument from Arbitrariness, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Simplicity and Theology.Don Fawkes & Tom Smythe - 1996 - Religious Studies 32 (2):259 - 270.
    Richard Swinburne has given a defense of arguments for the existence of God (and in particular of teleological arguments) in his book "The Existence of God" (1979/1991). This paper argues that such theistic arguments fail, and poses some general problems for theistic arguments. Swinburne's use of a principle of simplicity is not given adequate justification and, if justified, works against theism. There are adequate rebuttals to Swinburne's arguments that depend upon there being few particles of basic physics, universal laws of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Divine freedom and the choice of a world.Evan Fales - 1994 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 35 (2):65 - 88.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Infinite Value and the Best of All Possible Worlds.Nevin Climenhaga - 2018 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 97 (2):367-392.
    A common argument for atheism runs as follows: God would not create a world worse than other worlds he could have created instead. However, if God exists, he could have created a better world than this one. Therefore, God does not exist. In this paper I challenge the second premise of this argument. I argue that if God exists, our world will continue without end, with God continuing to create value-bearers, and sustaining and perfecting the value-bearers he has already created. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Deeply Disagreeing with Myself: Synchronic Intrapersonal Deep Disagreements.Patrick Bondy - 2020 - Topoi 40 (5):1225-1236.
    Interpersonal disagreement happens all the time. How to properly characterize interpersonal disagreement and how to respond to it are important problems, but the existence of such disagreements at least is obvious. The existence of intrapersonal disagreement, however, is another matter. On the one hand, we do change our minds sometimes, especially when new evidence comes in, and so there is a clear enough sense in which we can be characterized as having disagreements with our past selves. But what about synchronic (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Newcomb’s Problem.Kent Bach - 1987 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 17 (2):409-425.
    The more you think about it, the more baffling Newcomb's Problem becomes. To most people, at first it is obvious which solution is correct, but their confidence can be eroded easily. Only a puzzled few are torn between the two right from the start, and for years so was I. But at last, thanks to a certain metaargument, one solution came to seem obvious to me. And yet, imagining myself actually faced with Newcomb's choice, I started to worry that I (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Is Motivated Submaximization Good Enough for God?Klaas J. Kraay - 2021 - Religious Studies.
    In a recent article (Kraay 2013), I argued that some prominent responses to two important arguments for atheism invoke divine satisficing – and that the coherence and propriety of this notion have not been established. Chris Tucker (2016) agrees with my evaluation of divine satisficing, but disagrees with my exegesis of these responses. He argues that they should be understood as invoking motivated submaximization instead. After reviewing the dialectical situation to date, I assess whether motivated submaximization can be deployed in (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The problem of evil.Michael Tooley - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Philosophy of religion.Charles Taliaferro - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.