Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Playing at Being Gods.Antoni Abad I. Ninet - 2010 - Philosophia 38 (1):41-55.
    The present article commences analyzing the origins and influences of the religious discourse on the configuration of the modern constitutional discourse and the contributions of the jus-positivism in the consolidation of this sacred-civil language. The second issue is the definition of the U.S. Constitution as a mixed and not as a democratic constitution, with regard to the influences of Plato, Aristotle, Cicero and Polybius to the Drafters of the first modern constitutional text; stability and equilibrium took preference over democracy in (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Commentary on Lisi.Rober Tmayhew - 2000 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 16 (1):54-61.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dismantling the Master's House: A Hestian/Hermean Deconstruction of Classic Texts.Patricia J. Thompson - 1994 - Hypatia 9 (4):38-56.
    Classical philosophy adopts the standpoint of males in the Greek polis. The consequent adumbration of the standpoint of women and noncitizen men in the oikos, the household, has implications for feminist philosophy. Two systems of action are differentiated: the domestic economy protected by the goddess Hestia, and the political economy protected by Hermes. Shifting one's standpoint to include both the oikos and the polis offers an alternative to gender as the defining issue in feminist theory.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On the Standard Aversion to the Agrapha Dogmata.Thomas A. Szlezák - 2010 - Peitho 1 (1):57-74.
    The present paper deals with eight charges that are frequently leveled against any research that focuses on the agrapha dogmata. The charges are demonstrated to be completely unfounded and, therefore, duly dismissed. In particular, it is argued here that the phrase ta legomena is by no means to be understood as ironic. Consequently, the article rejects the very common picture of Plato as some sort of dogmatist and author of a fixed philosophical system. However, Plato’s philosophy is presented as rather (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Counterpoint to Modernity: Laws and Philosophical Reason in Plato’s Politicus.Costas Stratilatis - 2011 - Law and Critique 22 (1):15-37.
    The modern rationalist idea of rule of law, and modern rationalism in general, owes much to Plato and to Platonism. However, Plato’s stance towards the laws of the city is all but clear. On the one hand, we have the seemingly ‘totalitarian’ Plato of the Republic, a dialogue which defends the absolute authority of philosophical wisdom over all prescriptions that are ensuing from existing cities and their laws. On the other hand, we have the ‘more liberal-democratic’ Plato of the Laws, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • La proyección de Solón y de su poesía en la figura platónica del poeta legislador de "Leyes".Lucas Soares - 2018 - Revista de Filosofía 43 (2):165-181.
    En este trabajo me interesa abordar la figura del poeta legislador Solón, a fin de examinar la influencia que sus escritos pudieron haber ejercido sobre la concepción de la poesía forjada por Platón en _Leyes_. No se trata tanto de la poesía de Solón en sí misma como de lo que Platón supo leer en ella en términos de posibilidad para la conformación de un nuevo linaje poético. Partiendo de un breve examen de la figura de Solón y de algunos (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Killing Socrates: Plato¿s later thoughts on democracy.Christopher J. Rowe - 2001 - Journal of Hellenic Studies 121:63-76.
    The paper has two main aims, one larger and one slightly narrower. The larger aim is to undermine further a tendency that has dogged the interpretation of Platonic political philosophy in modern times, despite some dissenting voices: the tendency to begin from the assumption that Plato¿s thinking changed and developed over time, as if we already had privileged access to his biography. The slightly narrower aim is to reply to two charges of intellectual parricide made against Plato. The first is (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • L'Ébriété Démocratique la Critique Platonicienne de la Démocratie Dans Les Lois.Jean-François Pradeau - 2004 - Journal of Hellenic Studies 124:108-124.
    The aim of this study is to challenge the current scholarly consensus depicting Plato as having renounced the political ideal of his Republic, and modified it in favour of a in his last work, the Laws. The study shows that Plato's critique of democracy remains as firm in the Laws as it was in the Republic and the Statesman, refusing to concede any room to any form of popular sovereignty that could threaten the government of knowledge.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Plato's lawcode in context: rule by written law in Athens and Magnesia.Andrea Wilson Nightingale - 1999 - Classical Quarterly 49 (01):100-122.
    Perhaps more than any other dialogue, Plato's Laws demands a reading that is at once historical and philosophical. This text's conception of the ‘rule of law’ is best understood in its contemporary socio-political context; its philosophical discussion of this topic, in fact, can be firmly located in the political ideologies and institutions of fourth-century Greece. In this paper, I want to focus on the written lawcode created in the Laws in the context of the Athenian conception and practice of rule (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Dioniso en Platón: presencia y ausencia del dios de la máscara.David Hernández de la Fuente - 2015 - Isegoría 52:365-384.
    En este trabajo se propone una aproximación al uso filosófico del dios griego Dioniso en la obra de Platón, con especial referencia a la vertiente pedagógicopolítica del pensamiento platónico en la República y, sobre todo, en las Leyes. se discuten brevemente los trabajos anteriores que han tratado esta cuestión, incluidos los dos más recientes que versan sobre las Leyes y sobre la faceta filosófica de Dioniso, al hilo de una propuesta de lectura de las presencias y ausencias de Dioniso en (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Aequabilitas in Cicero's Political Theory, and the Greek Tradition of Proportional Justice.Elaine Fantham - 1973 - Classical Quarterly 23 (2):285-290.
    This inquiry starts from two passages in book 1 of Cicero'sde Re Publica, both concerned with the failings of democracy as a political form. The first occurs in Scipio Aemilianus' opening criticism of the three unmixed constitutions. The weakness of democracy is that (1. 43)cum omnia per populum geruntur quamvis iustum atque moderatum, tamenipsa aequabilitas est iniqua, cum habet nullos gradus dignitatis.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Divided Power and Ευνομια: Deliberative Procedures in Ancient Sparta.Alberto Esu - 2017 - Classical Quarterly 67 (2):353-373.
    Spartan institutions were pictured as a model of political stability from the Classical period onwards. The so-called Spartan ‘mirage’ did not involve only its constitutional order but also social and economic institutions. Xenophon begins hisConstitution of the Lacedaemoniansby associating Spartan fame with thepoliteiaset up by Lycurgus, which made the Laconian city the most powerful (δυνατωτάτη) and famous (ὀνομαστοτάτη)polisin Greece (Xen.Lac.1.1). In Aristotle'sPolitics, in which the assessment of Sparta is more complex and nuanced, one finds a critique of contemporary Spartan institutions (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Justice in the Laws, a Restatement: Why Plato Endorses Public Reason.Samuel Director - 2018 - Journal of the American Philosophical Association 4 (2):184-203.
    In the Laws, Plato argues that the legislator should attempt to persuade people to voluntarily obey the laws. This persuasion is accomplished through use of legislative preludes. Preludes (also called preambles) are short arguments written into the legal code, which precede laws and give reasons to follow them. In this paper, I argue that Plato’s use of persuasive preludes shows that he endorses the core features of a public reason theory of political justification. Many philosophers argue that Plato’s political philosophy (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Is it Wrong to Call Plato A Utilitarian?J. L. Creed - 1978 - Classical Quarterly 28 (2):349-365.
    Such is John Stuart Mill's succinct exposition of the core of utilitarian theory. A contemporary philosopher has aptly described utilitarianism as ‘the combination of two principles: (1)the consequentialist principlethat the rightness, or wrongness, of an action is determined by the goodness, or badness, of the results that flow from it and (2)the hedonist principlethat the only thing that is good in itself is pleasure and the only thing bad in itself is pain. Although the consequentialistprinciple has attracted the most attention (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Socratic Rhetoric in the Gorgias.Gabriela Roxana Carone - 2005 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 35 (2):221-241.
    Given that it seems uncontroversial that Socrates displays considerable contempt towards rhetoric in theGorgias,the title of this paper might strike one as an oxymoron. Indeed, a reading of the text has more than once encouraged scholars to posit an Opposition between the elenctic procedures championed by Socrates and the rhetorical procedures of his interlocutors. At least three features have been highlighted that seem to indicate this contrast:1.the Socratic interest in short questions and answers versus his interlocutors’ use of long speeches;2.the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Persuasion, Compulsion and Freedom in Plato's Laws.Christopher Bobonich - 1991 - Classical Quarterly 41 (2):365-388.
    One of the distinctions that Plato in the Laws stresses most heavily in his discussion of the proper relation between the individual citizen and the laws of the city is that between persuasion and compulsion. Law, Plato believes, should try to persuade rather than compel the citizens. Near the end of the fourth book of the Laws, the Athenian Stranger, Plato's spokesman in this dialogue, asks whether the lawgiver for their new city of Magnesia should in making laws ‘explain straightaway (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Wine and Catharsis_ of the Emotions in Plato's _Laws.Elizabeth Belfiore - 1986 - Classical Quarterly 36 (2):421-437.
    Plato's views on tragedy depend in large part on his views about the ethical consequences of emotional arousal. In theRepublic, Plato treats the desires we feel in everyday life to weep and feel pity as appetites exactly like those for food or sex, whose satisfactions are ‘replenishments’. Physical desire is not reprehensible in itself, but is simplynon-rational, not identical with reason but capable of being brought into agreement with it. Some desires, like that for simple and wholesome food, are in (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Dynamik und Stabilität der Tugend in Platons Nomoi.Jakub Jinek - 2016 - Aithér 8:66-89.
    Plato’s theory of virtue in the Laws could be striking for someone who is more familiar with Aristotle’s ethics for conceptual complementarity between the two positions (contrary emotions, the ordering element of reason, virtue as a mean which lies between two forms of vice, typically linked to excessive actions, etc.). Plato’s theory, however, still differs from that of Aristotle in two crutial points. First, the source of emotional dynamism is, according to Plato, supraindividual as far as the psyche is a (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Alive Beyond Death! Ricoeur and the Immortalizing Narrative of the Self.Tracy Llanera - 2010 - Philosophical Frontiers: A Journal of Emerging Thought 5 (1):37-42.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Politics of Virtue in Plato's "Laws".John Melvin Armstrong - 1998 - Dissertation, The University of Arizona
    This dissertation identifies and explains four major contributions of the Laws and related late dialogues to Plato's moral and political philosophy. -/- Chapter 1: I argue that Plato thinks the purpose of laws and other social institutions is the happiness of the city. A happy city is one in which the city's parts, i.e. the citizens, are unified under the rule of intelligence. Unlike the citizens of the Republic, the citizens of the Laws can all share the same true judgments (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Acerca de la disposición favorable para con Los inmigrantes según las leyes de platón. La igualdad económica como contraargumento.Sandra Maceri - 2009 - Signos Filosóficos 11 (22):123-145.
    La ciudad de amigos que Platón pretende fundar en Las Leyes tiene como pilares la eliminación de los extremos de la riqueza y de la pobreza, por una parte, y la educación de todos los sectores sociales, por otra. Si bien este basamento suele ser reconocido por los especialistas, la legislación sobre..
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark