Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Grace de Laguna: Why Forgotten as a Philosopher?Sophia Connell - 2022 - Australasian Philosophical Review 6 (1):33-38.
    Grace de Laguna’s philosophical work was bold and original. She was also able to connect together seemingly disparate strands of the pragmatic, metaphysical and psychological research going on around her, as Joel Katzav shows in his paper. This commentary gives some historical background to her academic career in an attempt to explain how she could have been forgotten as a philosopher. Social and institutional factors led to her work not being recognized when she wrote and thus sinking into obscurity in (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • VI—Should We Believe Philosophical Claims on Testimony?Keith Allen - 2019 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 119 (2):105-125.
    This paper considers whether we should believe philosophical claims on the basis of testimony in light of related debates about aesthetic and moral testimony. It is argued that we should not believe philosophical claims on testimony, and different explanations of why we should not are considered. It is suggested that the reason why we should not believe philosophical claims on testimony might be that philosophy is not truth-directed.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Quantification and Paradox.Edward Ferrier - 2018 - Dissertation, University of Massachusetts Amherst
    I argue that absolutism, the view that absolutely unrestricted quantification is possible, is to blame for both the paradoxes that arise in naive set theory and variants of these paradoxes that arise in plural logic and in semantics. The solution is restrictivism, the view that absolutely unrestricted quantification is not possible. -/- It is generally thought that absolutism is true and that restrictivism is not only false, but inexpressible. As a result, the paradoxes are blamed, not on illicit quantification, but (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • B-Theory and Time Biases.Sayid Bnefsi - 2019 - In Patrick Blackburn, Per Hasle & Peter Øhrstrøm (eds.), Logic and Philosophy of Time: Further Themes from Prior. Aalborg University Press. pp. 41-52.
    We care not only about what experiences we have, but when we have them too. However, on the B-theory of time, something’s timing isn’t an intrinsic way for that thing to be or become. Given B-theory, should we be rationally indifferent about the timing per se of an experience? In this paper, I argue that B-theorists can justify time-biased preferences for pains to be past rather than present and for pleasures to be present rather than past. In support of this (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Mill on logic.David Godden - 2016 - In Christopher Macleod & Dale E. Miller (eds.), A Companion to Mill. Hoboken: John Wiley & Sons, Inc.. pp. 175-191.
    Working within the broad lines of general consensus that mark out the core features of John Stuart Mill’s (1806–1873) logic, as set forth in his A System of Logic (1843–1872), this chapter provides an introduction to Mill’s logical theory by reviewing his position on the relationship between induction and deduction, and the role of general premises and principles in reasoning. Locating induction, understood as a kind of analogical reasoning from particulars to particulars, as the basic form of inference that is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Russell and Husserl (1905–1918): The Not-So-Odd Couple.Nikolay Milkov - 2016 - In Peter Stone (ed.), Bertrand Russell’s Life and Legacy. Wilmington, Delaware, United States: Vernon Press. pp. 73-96.
    Historians of philosophy commonly regard as antipodal Bertrand Russell and Edmund Husserl, the founding fathers of analytic philosophy and phenomenology. This paper, however, establishes that during a formative phase in both of their careers Russell and Husserl shared a range of seminal ideas. In particular, the essay adduces clear cases of family resemblance between Husserl’s and Russell’s philosophy during their middle period, which spanned the years 1905 through 1918. The paper thus challenges the received view of Husserl’s relation to early (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Russell Contra Sense/Reference, the ‘Mont Blanc’ Correspondence.Clare Hay - 2022 - History and Philosophy of Logic 44 (4):476-490.
    It is argued that Russell before 1905 saw no value in Frege's sense/reference distinction. This is clearest in the Mont Blanc correspondence. It is argued that Russell and Frege failed to engage because Frege lacked a grasp on the internal/external relations distinction. For Russell sense is either an external relation, objectionably separating out thought and reference, or an internal relation, so what is thought is altered such that we do not know what we are talking about. The novelty of the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The end of what? Phenomenology vs. speculative realism.Dan Zahavi - 2016 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 24 (3):289-309.
    Phenomenology has recently come under attack from proponents of speculative realism. In this paper, I present and assess the criticism, and argue that it is either superficial and simplistic or lacks novelty.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Primitivist theories of truth: Their history and prospects.Jeremy Wyatt - 2022 - Philosophy Compass 17 (6):e12832.
    Primitivists about truth maintain that truth cannot be analysed in more fundamental terms. Defences of primitivism date back to the early years of analytic philosophy, being offered by G.E. Moore, Bertrand Russell, and Gottlob Frege. In more recent years, a number of contemporary philosophers—including Donald Davidson, Ernest Sosa, Trenton Merricks, Douglas Patterson, and Jamin Asay—have followed suit, defending their own versions of primitivism. I'll begin by offering a brief history of primitivism, situating each of these views within the landscape of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Commentary on Price.Charlotte Witt - 1996 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 12 (1):310-316.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Russellian Acquaintance and Frege’s Puzzle.Donovan Wishon - 2016 - Mind 126 (502):321-370.
    In this paper, I argue that a number of recent Russell interpreters, including Evans, Davidson, Campbell, and Proops, mistakenly attribute to Russell what I call ‘the received view of acquaintance’: the view that acquaintance safeguards us from misidentifying the objects of our acquaintance. I contend that Russell’s discussions of phenomenal continua cases show that he does not accept the received view of acquaintance. I also show that the possibility of misidentifying the objects of acquaintance should be unsurprising given underappreciated aspects (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Radical Empiricism, Neutral Monism, and the Elements of Mind.Donovan Wishon - 2021 - The Monist 104 (1):125-151.
    Neutral monism is the view that both ‘mind’ and ‘matter’ are grounded in a more fundamental form of reality that is intrinsically neither mental nor material. It has often been treated as an odd fringe theory deserving of at most a footnote in the broader philosophical debates. Yet such attitudes do a grave disservice to its sophistications and significance for late nineteenth and early twentieth-century philosophy of mind and psychology. This paper sheds light on this neglected view by situating it (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Incomplete Symbols and Russell's Proof.W. Kent Wilson - 1980 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 10 (2):233 - 250.
    Russell urged that some phrases having no meaning in isolation could nonetheless, Contribute to the meaning of sentences in which they occur. In the case of definite descriptive phrases, A proof is offered. It is argued that russell's proof is valid, Contrary to some commentators. Proper understanding of the notion of "incomplete symbol" plays a key role in the assessment of the argument, As well as in full appreciation of the radical departure of russell's analysis from "surface" grammar.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Sense Certainty’, or Why Russell had no ‘Knowledge by Acquaintance.Kenneth R. Westphal - 2002 - Hegel Bulletin 23 (1-2):110-123.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Three Views concerning Human Freedom.John Watkins - 1974 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures 8:200-228.
    Ultimately, the only good reason for restricting the freedom of responsible adults is to protect other people's freedom, to increase the overall enjoyment of freedom.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Three Views concerning Human Freedom.John Watkins - 1974 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures 8:200-228.
    Ultimately, the only good reason for restricting the freedom of responsible adults is to protect other people's freedom, to increase the overall enjoyment of freedom.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Paradoxical Aspects of the Russellian Conception of Existence.J. L. Usó-Doménech, J. A. Nescolarde-Selva & H. Gash - 2023 - Foundations of Science 28 (3):911-925.
    In this paper, the authors try to clarify the relations between Meinong’s and Russell's thoughts on the ontological ideas of existence. The Meinongian theory on non-existent objects does not in itself violate the principle of non-contradiction, since the problem that this hypothesis offers to the theory of definite descriptions is not so much a logical problem as an ontological problem. To demonstrate this we will establish what we believe are the two main theses basic to the theory of descriptions: the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Forgotten Vintage.R. E. Tully - 1988 - Dialogue 27 (2):299-.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Identity Metaphysics.Galen Strawson - 2021 - The Monist 104 (1):60-90.
    Identity metaphysics finds identity or unity where other metaphysical theories find difference or diversity. It denies the fundamentality of ontological distinctions that other theories treat as fundamental. It’s opposed to separatism, which mistakes natural conceptual distinctions for ground-floor ontological differences. It proposes that the distinctions between the concepts substance, object, quality, property, process, state, and event are metaphysically superficial; so too the distinctions between the concepts energy, lawsofnature, force, causation, power, and naturalnecessity. So too the distinction between these two sets (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Identity Metaphysics.Galen Strawson - 2021 - The Monist 104 (1):30-60.
    Identity metaphysics finds identity or unity where other metaphysical theories find difference or diversity. It denies the fundamentality of ontological distinctions that other theories treat as fundamental. It’s opposed to separatism, which mistakes natural conceptual distinctions for ground-floor ontological differences. It proposes that the distinctions between the concepts SUBSTANCE, OBJECT, QUALITY, PROPERTY, PROCESS, STATE, and EVENT are metaphysically superficial; so too the distinctions between the concepts ENERGY, LAWSOFNATURE, FORCE, CAUSATION, POWER, and NATURALNECESSITY. So too the distinction between these two sets (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • From Russell's Paradox to the Theory of Judgement: Wittgenstein and Russell on the Unity of the Proposition.Graham Stevens - 2004 - Theoria 70 (1):28-61.
    It is fairly well known that Wittgenstein's criticisms of Russell's multiple‐relation theory of judgement had a devastating effect on the latter's philosophical enterprise. The exact nature of those criticisms however, and the explanation for the severity of their consequences, has been a source of confusion and disagreement amongst both Russell and Wittgenstein scholars. In this paper, I offer an interpretation of those criticisms which shows them to be consonant with Wittgenstein's general critique of Russell's conception of logic and which serves (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Bald-faced lies! Lying without the intent to deceive.Roy Sorensen - 2007 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 88 (2):251-264.
    Surprisingly, the fact that the speaker is lying is sometimes common knowledge between everyone involved. Strangely, we condemn these bald-faced lies more severely than disguised lies. The wrongness of lying springs from the intent to deceive – just the feature missing in the case of bald-faced lies. These puzzling lies arise systematically when assertions are forced. Intellectual duress helps to explain another type of non-deceptive false assertion : lying to yourself. In the end, I conclude that the apparent intensity of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   100 citations  
  • The principle of parsimony.Elliott Sober - 1981 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 32 (2):145-156.
  • Theological Underpinnings of the Modern Philosophy of Mathematics.Vladislav Shaposhnikov - 2016 - Studies in Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric 44 (1):147-168.
    The study is focused on the relation between theology and mathematics in the situation of increasing secularization. My main concern in the second part of this paper is the early-twentieth-century foundational crisis of mathematics. The hypothesis that pure mathematics partially fulfilled the functions of theology at that time is tested on the views of the leading figures of the three main foundationalist programs: Russell, Hilbert and Brouwer.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The experience and knowledge of time, through Russell and Moore.Jack Shardlow - 2023 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 31 (2):231-250.
    This paper develops the account of our experience and knowledge of time put forward by Russell in his Theory of Knowledge manuscript. While Russell ultimately abandons the project after it receives severe criticism from Wittgenstein (though several chapters derived from it appear as articles in The Monist), in producing this manuscript time, and particularly the notion of the present time, play a central role in Russell’s account of experience. In the present discussion, I propose to focus largely on Russell’s writing (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Which Arithmetization for Which Logicism? Russell on Relations and Quantities in The Principles of Mathematics.Sébastien Gandon - 2008 - History and Philosophy of Logic 29 (1):1-30.
    This article aims first at showing that Russell's general doctrine according to which all mathematics is deducible ‘by logical principles from logical principles’ does not require a preliminary reduction of all mathematics to arithmetic. In the Principles, mechanics (part VII), geometry (part VI), analysis (part IV–V) and magnitude theory (part III) are to be all directly derived from the theory of relations, without being first reduced to arithmetic (part II). The epistemological importance of this point cannot be overestimated: Russell's logicism (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Scott Soames, philosophical analysis in the twentieth century: Volume 1: The dawn of analysis. [REVIEW]R. M. Sainsbury - 2006 - Philosophical Studies 129 (3):637 - 643.
    The review praises the philosophical quality, but is less enthusiastic about the scholarship and historical accuracy.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Book Reviews. [REVIEW]Victor Rodych - 1995 - Philosophia Mathematica 3 (3):271-288.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What we must pass over in silence.Patrick Quinn - 2022 - Claridades. Revista de Filosofía 14 (2):49-69.
    Ludwig Wittgenstein’s and Bertrand Russell’s views on mysticism show their intense interest in this subject and how they explored its nature and possibilities. Wittgenstein, who had abandoned his Catholic faith as a teenager, became a religious searcher, which began from his fears of the terrors of war. He had enlisted as a soldier to fight for Austro-Hungary during which his terror of war led him to pray to God for refuge. The fortuitous discovery of Leo Tolstoy’s book, The Gospel in (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Unravelling the world knot: Scientists and philosophers on the mind–brain controversy. [REVIEW]Roland Puccetti - 1978 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 29 (1):61-68.
  • The problem of atomism.Heinz Post - 1975 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 26 (1):19-26.
  • Pragmatisme Logique et Probabilisme Radical dans la Philosophie Italienne du XXe Siècle.Paolo Parrini - 2011 - Revue de Synthèse 132 (2):191-211.
    L’article esquisse les traits principaux d’un courant philosophique qui a rencontré en Italie bien des difficultés, malgré l’importance reconnue de ses représentants. Le texte illustre les idées qui sont à la base du pragmatisme logique et méthodologique de Giovanni Vailati et Mario Calderoni, idées qui auraient refait surface dans le débat international à propos du principe de vérification et du concept d’analyticité. Sont également abordés les liens entre ces idées et le développement de la conception subjective des probabilités chez Bruno (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Aristotle and Aquinas on Cognition.Joseph Owens - 1991 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 17 (sup1):103-123.
    There is little need today to be apologetic about making Aristotle the basis for a philosophical discussion on human cognition. Interest in the Stagirite is in fact on the upsurge: interest in Aristotle not merely as a great thinker who lived in a particular epoch of time, but more pointedly as a philosopher who has much to offer for the promotion of serious thinking in our own day. In this regard I might merely refer to some straws that are indicative (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The epistemology of J. M. Keynes.Rod O'donnell - 1990 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 41 (3):333-350.
    This paper has two objectives, neither previously attempted in the published literature—first, to outline J. M. Keynes's theory of knowledge in some detail, and, secondly, to justify the contention that his epistemology is a variety of rationalism, and not, as many have asserted, a form of empiricism. Keynes's attitude to empirical data is also analysed as well as his views on prediction and theory choice. 1This paper is partly based on ideas initially advanced in O'Donnell [1982], a revised and expanded (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On Rhetoric and the School of Philosophy Without Tears.Stuart J. Murray - 2017 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 50 (4):528-551.
    In the introduction to his recent book outlining a "deep rhetoric" that can affirm rhetoric's "philosophical foundations," James Crosswhite celebrates a remark made by the late Henry Johnstone, the founding and long-time editor of Philosophy and Rhetoric. Johnstone, claims Crosswhite, "once suggested that rhetoric was an attempt to be 'philosophy without tears'". The passage to which Crosswhite refers appears in Johnstone's foreword to the book Rhetoric and Philosophy, a collection of essays edited by Richard Cherwitz. There, in a bungled bid (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Introduction: What is Ontology for?Katherine Munn - 2008 - In Katherine Munn & Barry Smith (eds.), Applied Ontology: An Introduction. Walter de Gruyter. pp. 7-19.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Applied Ontology: An Introduction.Katherine Munn & Barry Smith (eds.) - 2008 - Frankfurt: ontos.
    Ontology is the philosophical discipline which aims to understand how things in the world are divided into categories and how these categories are related together. This is exactly what information scientists aim for in creating structured, automated representations, called 'ontologies,' for managing information in fields such as science, government, industry, and healthcare. Currently, these systems are designed in a variety of different ways, so they cannot share data with one another. They are often idiosyncratically structured, accessible only to those who (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Russell's completeness proof.Peter Milne - 2008 - History and Philosophy of Logic 29 (1):31-62.
    Bertrand Russell’s 1906 article ‘The Theory of Implication’ contains an algebraic weak completeness proof for classical propositional logic. Russell did not present it as such. We give an exposition of the proof and investigate Russell’s view of what he was about, whether he could have appreciated the proof for what it is, and why there is no parallel of the proof in Principia Mathematica.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Book Review: Mauro Luiz Engelmann, Reading Wittgenstein’s Tractatus. [REVIEW]Nikolay Milkov - 2022 - Nordic Wittgenstein Review 11.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Analytical Critiques of Whitehead's Metaphysics.Leemon McHenry & George W. Shields - 2016 - Journal of the American Philosophical Association 2 (3):483-503.
    ABSTRACT:Analytic philosophers have criticized A. N. Whitehead's metaphysics for being obscure, yet several such philosophers have espoused positions in metaphysics and philosophy of mind that were advanced by Whitehead in the 1920s. In this paper, we evaluate the merits and demerits of these criticisms by Bertrand Russell, W. V. Quine, Karl Popper, and others and then demonstrate the affinities and contrasts in the positions advanced by Galen Strawson, David Chalmers, Thomas Nagel, and Whitehead regarding so-called ‘analytic panexperientialism’.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The semantics of singular terms.Gordon Matheson - 1962 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 27 (4):439-466.
  • Wilson on Relativism and Teaching.Jim Mackenzie - 1987 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 21 (1):119-130.
    Jim Mackenzie; Wilson on Relativism and Teaching, Journal of Philosophy of Education, Volume 21, Issue 1, 30 May 2006, Pages 119–130, https://doi.org/10.1111/j.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Cambridge Revolt Against Idealism: Was There Ever an Eden?Fraser Macbride - 2012 - Metaphilosophy 43 (1-2):135-146.
    According to one creation myth, analytic philosophy emerged in Cambridge when Moore and Russell abandoned idealism in favour of naive realism: every word stood for something; it was only after “the Fall,” Russell's discovery of his theory of descriptions, that they realized some complex phrases (“the present King of France”) didn't stand for anything. It has become a commonplace of recent scholarship to object that even before the Fall, Russell acknowledged that such phrases may fail to denote. But we need (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Dahlbeck and Pure Ontology.Jim Mackenzie - 2016 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 48 (9).
    This article responds to Johan Dahlbeck’s ‘Towards a pure ontology: Children’s bodies and morality’, 2014, pp. 8–23). His arguments from Nietzsche and Spinoza do not carry the weight he supposes, and the conclusions he draws from them about pedagogy would be ill-advised in practice.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A reply on behalf of the relativist to mark Mason's justification of universal ethical principles.Jim Mackenzie - 2007 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 39 (6):657–675.
    Mark Mason, in his ‘A Justification, After the Postmodern Turn, of Universal Ethical Principles and Educational Ideals’ Educational Philosophy and Theory, 37 , attempts to justify transcultural multiculturalism. In this paper I argue that he fails to refute moral relativism, and that multiculturalism as he interprets it is not morally acceptable.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the “Gray’s Elegy” Argument and its Bearing on Frege’s Theory of Sense.James Levine - 2004 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 69 (2):251–295.
    In his recent book, "The Metaphysicians of Meaning" (2000), Gideon Makin argues that in the so-called "Gray's Elegy" argument (the GEA) in "On Denoting", Russell provides decisive arguments against not only his own theory of denoting concepts but also Frege's theory of sense. I argue that by failing to recognize fundamental differences between the two theories, Makin fails to recognize that the GEA has less force against Frege's theory than against Russell's own earlier theory. While I agree with many aspects (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Sprachphilosophie, kopernikanische wende und 'linguistic turn'.J. Leilich - 1985 - Bijdragen 46 (2):141-153.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A renaissance of empiricism in the recent philosophy of mathematics.Imre Lakatos - 1976 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 27 (3):201-223.
  • Russell on Negative Judgement.Anssi Korhonen - 2020 - Topoi 39 (3):727-742.
    This paper concerns Bertrand Russell’s changing views on negative judgement. ‘Negative judgement’ is considered in the context of three theories of judgement that Russell put forth at different times: a dual relation theory ; a multiple relation theory ; a psychological theory of judgement. Four issues are singled out for a more detailed discussion: quality dualism versus quality monism, that is, the question whether judgement comes in two kinds, acceptance and rejection, or whether there is only one judgement-quality ; the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Dialectical Contradictions and Classical Formal Logic.Inoue Kazumi - 2014 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 28 (2):113-132.
    A dialectical contradiction can be appropriately described within the framework of classical formal logic. It is in harmony with the law of noncontradiction. According to our definition, two theories make up a dialectical contradiction if each of them is consistent and their union is inconsistent. It can happen that each of these two theories has an intended model. Plenty of examples are to be found in the history of science.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark