Switch to: References

Citations of:

Philosophy of social science

Englewood Cliffs, N.J.,: Prentice-Hall (1966)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Re-politicising Philosophy of Science: A Continuing Challenge for Social Epistemology.Kei Yoshida - 2012 - Social Epistemology 26 (3-4):365-378.
    The aim of this paper is to investigate how we can reunite social philosophy and philosophy of science to address problems in science and technology. First, referring to Don Howard?s, George Reisch?s, and Philip Mirowski?s works, I shall briefly explain how philosophy of science was depoliticised during the cold war. Second, I shall examine Steve Fuller?s criticism of Thomas Kuhn. Third, I shall scrutinise Philip Kitcher?s view of well-ordered science. Fourth, I shall emphasise the importance of autonomy and argue that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Progress in the development of a formal lexicon for the social sciences.Robert J. Wolfson - 1981 - Synthese 46 (3):455 - 465.
  • Idealisierte erklärungen.Manfred Tietzel - 1986 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 17 (2):315-321.
    Idealized explanations are the one subtype of incomplete explanations which is most frequently used in the empirical sciences and at the same time least analyzed in philosphy of science. It is argued that idealized explanations, while having the same logical structure as adequate explanations, differ from these in the mode of validity of the argument. Whereas an adequate explanation shows why the occurrence of some event had to be expected, an idealized explanation argues that a certain event would occur if (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On our knowledge of the social world.Stuart Silvers - 1967 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 10 (1-4):96-97.
  • Economic Methodology.Steven Rappaport - 1988 - Economics and Philosophy 4 (1):110.
  • From an intentionalist perspective.Richard L. Smith - 1974 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 17 (1-4):1 – 22.
    In order to expound and defend the intentionalist thesis that human actions are intentionally determined by persons, selves, or agents themselves I first argue that teleological explanation, even though it is consistent with physicalism and scientifically respectable in the sense of being an attempt to establish the conditions under which things and events occur and to formulate laws that express such dependencies, is not exactly coordinate with and replaceable by mechanistic explanation. Then, I argue that living human beings must be (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Approximate truth, idealization, and ontology.Robert John Schwartz - 1990 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 28 (3):409-425.
  • Theory choice in a two-level science.Geoffrey Sampson - 1975 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 26 (4):303-318.
  • Dialectics, Problematics.Kay Salleh - 1983 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 13 (1):55-62.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The nature of scientific models : Formal V material analogy.Michael Ruse - 1973 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 3 (1):63-80.
  • The concept of action in the social sciences.D. Rubinstein - 1977 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 7 (2):209–236.
  • The Modal View of Economic Models.Steven Rappaport - 1989 - Philosophica 44:61-80.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Thoughts are facts in possible worlds, truths are facts of a given world.Leszek NowAK - 1991 - Dialectica 45 (4):273-288.
    Mentalism preserves the triad: brain's state — thought — state of affairs whereas phy‐sicalism identifies the former two elements of it. Both stands meet the famous difficulties. But these presuppose ontological actualism. On the ground of ontological possibilism, claiming the existence of all possible worlds, one may identify a thought with the corresponding state of affairs in a possible world. Yet, possibilism turns out to be too narrow to carry such an identification and requires a significant generalization.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Some notes on the nature of methodological indeterminacy.Steven I. Miller & Marcel Fredericks - 1991 - Synthese 88 (3):359 - 378.
    This paper is an attempt to extend the meaning of the concept of indeterminacy for the human sciences. The authors do this by coining the term methodological indeterminacy and arguing that indeterminacy is better understood when linked to specific methodological techniques. Paradoxically, while specific research techniques demonstrate that the issue of indeterminacy is complex, yielding the possibility of types and degrees, it does not eliminate the problem of translation first raised by Quine. However, the authors go on to argue that, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Some comments on the projectibility of anthropological hypotheses: Samoa briefly revisited.Steven J. Miller & Marcel Fredericks - 1989 - Erkenntnis 30 (3):279 - 299.
    The purpose of this article is to examine the applicability of the theory of projection for Anthropological hypotheses. The claim is made that Goodman's classic statement of the problem does not apply in its entirety to actual Anthropological hypotheses. The recent Freeman-Mead debate is employed as a framework for the discussion, illustrating that the issue of projectibility, while central for the social sciences, is best used as a backdrop to illustrate several important methodological problems. For Anthropology, and other related social (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Sociology of Education and the Education of Teachers.D. R. McNamara - 1972 - British Journal of Educational Studies 20 (2):137 - 147.
  • Sociology of education and the education of teachers.D. R. McNamara - 1972 - British Journal of Educational Studies 20 (2):137-147.
  • An explicative model of theory testing.Michael Martin - 1970 - Zeitschrift Für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 1 (2):228-242.
    The official view of theory testing in the philosophy of science, the deductive model, does not reflect the way ambiguous, vague and ill formulated theories are tested. A new model of theory testing, the explicative model, is outlined which reflects how such theories are tested. This model is illustrated in the actual testing of psychoanalysis, a typical case of an ambiguous, vague and ill formulated theory and is contrasted with Kuhn's notion of the articulation of a paradigm.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A note on fundamental theory and idealizations in economics and physics.Hans Lind - 1993 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 44 (3):493-503.
    Modern economics, with its use of advanced mathematical methods, is often looked upon as the physics of the social sciences. It is here argued that deductive analyses are more important in economics than in physics, because the economists more seldom can confirm phenomenological laws directly. The economist has to use assumptions from fundamental theory when trying to bridge the gap between observations and phenomenological laws. Partly as a result of the difficulties of establishing phenomenological laws, analyses of idealized 'model-economies' play (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Winch and instrumental pluralism: A response to my critics.Berel Dov Lerner - 1998 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 28 (2):312-320.
  • II. Understanding in the social sciences revisited.James W. van Evra - 1969 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 12 (1-4):347-349.
    Rolf Gruner's article on the role of understanding in the social sciences casts rational understanding as the aim of the social sciences. Even though he opts for a non?controversial methodology for the social sciences, his view still commits the social sciences to seeking the reproduction of reality rather than the explanation of it.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Relativism, reality and philosophy.John Horton - 2000 - History of the Human Sciences 13 (1):19-36.
    This article explores Peter Winch’s account of the relationship between language and reality. It defends Winch against some common misunderstandings of his views but identifies two problematic areas. The first concerns the internal coherence of his account of philosophy. The second relates to the issue of rejecting particular ways of life or cultural practices as erroneous or illusory. One source of these problems is a tension between Winch’s official conception of philosophy and his own commitment to ‘defending’ the plurality of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Towards a General Theory of Reduction. Part III: Cross-Categorical Reduction.C. A. Hooker - 1981 - Dialogue 20 (3):496-529.
    Any theory of reduction that goes only so far as carried in Parts I and II does only half the job. Prima facie at least, there are cases of would-be reduction which seem torn between two conflicting intuitions. On the one side there is a strong intuition that reduction is involved, and a strongly retentive reduction at that. On the other side it seems that the concepts at one level cross-classify those at the other level, so that there is no (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • A Case Study of Normal Research in Theoretical Economics.Hans Lind - 1992 - Economics and Philosophy 8 (1):83.
    Theoretical works in economics usually have a core consisting of proofs that a “model-economy” has certain properties. The economist constructs a model that can be looked on as a description of an economy, and then proves that certain relations hold in this economy and/or that certain relations in this economy depend on certain specific characteristics. The model-economy is usually described as simplified or idealized.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Foundations for the social sciences explanation: Revisiting NiklasLuhmann’s contructivism.Jorge Gibert Galassi & Juan Pablo Venables - 2020 - Humanities Journal of Valparaiso 16:191-214.
    In this work, it is argued that one of the foundations of NiklasLuhmann’s theory of social systems, namely that it has no ontology, would prevent the elaboration of explanations in sociology. Because the theory has a formal-logical foundation, which does not presuppose ontology, there are insurmountable obstacles to achieving this objective. For this reason, it is valid to wonder about the merit of a theory that, after 20 years, insists on not aligning itself with ontological premises in a robust way (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On Scriven on ‘Verstehen’.James W. Van Evra - 1971 - Theory and Decision 1 (4):377-381.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Reflections on Epistemic-Ontological Alignment in Theorizing Process: the Case of RBV.Júlio César da Costa Júnior, Leandro da Silva Nascimento, Taciana de Barros Jerônimo, Jackeline Amantino de Andrade & Marcos André Mendes Primo - 2022 - Philosophy of Management 21 (2):179-198.
    Although from a philosophical perspective, many reflections can be brought up about the theorizing process, in this essay, we aim to reflect on the importance of the alignment between ontology and epistemology. This is particularly relevant because deeper discussions about the philosophical roots that underlay the theorizing processes remain as a lack in organizational and management studies. To support our work, we adopted the epistemic-ontological alignment model as a conceptual tool and the Resource-Based View (RBV) and some of its questionings (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Scientific values and moral education in the teaching of science.Jeffrey Burkhardt - 1999 - Perspectives on Science 7 (1):87-110.
    : Implicit instruction about values occurs throughout scientific communication, whether in the university classroom or in the larger public forum. The concern of this paper is that the kind of values education that occurs includes "reverse moral education," the idea that moral considerations are at best extra scientific if not simply irrational. The (a)moral education that many scientists unwittingly foist on their "students" undergirds the scientific establishment's typical responses to larger social issues: "Huff!" In this paper I explain the nature (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Logical Structure of Applied Social Science.GÜnther E. Braun - 1982 - Theory and Decision 14 (1):1.
  • Foreign policy as a goal directed activity.Paul A. Anderson - 1984 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 14 (2):159-181.
  • Scholarship as a Vocation: Reflections on the Past and Future of Social Science.Zhasmina Tacheva - 2016 - Emerging Perspectives: School of Management Review 1 (1):5-19.
    This essay seeks to expose readers from the social sciences to current debates in their fields, beyond the discussions of induction and deduction one learns about in a typical research methods course. It provides glimpses of social science from its dawn in 17th century empiricism, through the rise of postpositivism and antipositivism, to the infamous “science wars” in the 1990s, and expresses a hope for a broader and more inclusive future. Specifically, the paper compares the traditional positivist method of scientific (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Popper's Thesis of the Unity of Scientific Method: Method Versus Techniques.Carlos Verdugo - 2009 - In Zuzana Parusniková & R. S. Cohen (eds.), Rethinking Popper. Springer. pp. 155--160.
  • Is the Viable System Model of organization inimical to the concept of human freedom?Rod Thomas - unknown
    This paper examines the sensitivity of Stafford Beer’s Viable System Model of organization to the concept of human freedom. The paper notes the many critics who have suggested that the Viable System Model is inimical to human freedom and their especial reference to its application to the social economy of Chile in the early 1970s. Drawing on the work of philosophers, a conceptual analysis of freedom is provided that suggests a complex ordinary language usage of the term. At least three (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark