Switch to: References

Citations of:

Animal rights and human morality

Buffalo, N.Y.: Prometheus Books (1981)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Perspectival pluralism for animal welfare.Walter Veit & Heather Browning - 2021 - European Journal for Philosophy of Science 11 (1):1-14.
    Animal welfare has a long history of disregard. While in recent decades the study of animal welfare has become a scientific discipline of its own, the difficulty of measuring animal welfare can still be vastly underestimated. There are three primary theories, or perspectives, on animal welfare - biological functioning, natural living and affective state. These come with their own diverse methods of measurement, each providing a limited perspective on an aspect of welfare. This paper describes a perspectival pluralist account of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Health and Welfare in Animals and Humans.Lennart Nordenfelt - 2011 - Acta Biotheoretica 59 (2):139-152.
    This paper contains a brief comparative analysis of some philosophical and scientific discourses on human and animal health and welfare, focusing mainly on the welfare of sentient animals. The paper sets forth two kinds of proposals for the analysis of animal welfare which do not appear in the contemporary philosophical discussion of human welfare, viz. the coping theory of welfare and the theory of welfare in terms of natural behaviour. These proposals are scrutinized in the light of some similar theories (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Motivational Bases of Attitudes Toward Animals.Adelma M. Hills - 1993 - Society and Animals 1 (2):111-128.
    The need for a theoretical grounding of the human-animal relationship is addressed from the perspective of the motivational bases of attitudes toward animals. Building on recent developments in attitude theory, and integrating themes from the historical and cultural background to Western attitudes, a model is developed that proposes three fundamental motivational bases, where responses to animals depend on instrumental self interest, empathylidentification, or people's beliefs and values about the nature and status of animals. Initial empirical studies using the model revealed (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Nonhuman Animals: Not Necessarily Saints or Sinners.C. E. Abbate - 2014 - Between the Species 17 (1):1-30.
    Higher-order thought theories maintain that consciousness involves the having of higher-order thoughts about mental states. In response to these theories of consciousness, an attempt is often made to illustrate that nonhuman animals possess said consciousness, overlooking an alarming consequence: attributing higher-order thought to nonhuman animals might entail that they should be held morally accountable for their actions. I argue that moral responsibility requires more than higher-order thought: moral agency requires a specific higher-order thought which concerns a belief about the rightness (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Case for Animal Rights.Tom Regan - 2004 - Univ of California Press.
    More than twenty years after its original publication, _The Case for Animal Rights _is an acknowledged classic of moral philosophy, and its author is recognized as the intellectual leader of the animal rights movement. In a new and fully considered preface, Regan responds to his critics and defends the book's revolutionary position.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   451 citations  
  • Quality Time: Temporal and Other Aspects of Ethical Principles Based on a “Life Worth Living”. [REVIEW]James Yeates - 2012 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 25 (4):607-624.
    The evaluation of whether an animal has a life worth living (LWL) has been suggested as a useful concept for farm animal policymaking. But there are a number of different ways in which the concept could be applied. This paper attempts to identify and evaluate candidate ethical principles based on the concept. It suggests that an appropriate principle by which to apply the concept is one that (1) is framed in terms of preventing an animal having a life worth avoiding (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Companion Animal Ethics: A Special Area of Moral Theory and Practice?James Yeates & Julian Savulescu - 2017 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 20 (2):347-359.
    Considerations of ethical questions regarding pets should take into account the nature of human-pet relationships, in particular the uniquely combined features of mutual companionship, quasi-family-membership, proximity, direct contact, privacy, dependence, and partiality. The approaches to ethical questions about pets should overlap with those of animal ethics and family ethics, and so need not represent an isolated field of enquiry, but rather the intersection of those more established fields. This intersection, and the questions of how we treat our pets, present several (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Death is a welfare issue.James W. Yeates - 2010 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 23 (3):229-241.
    It is commonly asserted that “death is not a welfare issue” and this has been reflected in welfare legislation and policy in many countries. However, this creates a conflict for many who consider animal welfare to be an appropriate basis for decision-making in animal ethics but also consider that an animal’s death is ethically significant. To reconcile these viewpoints, this paper attempts to formulate an account of death as a welfare issue. Welfare issues are issues that refer to evaluations concerning (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • The Harm of Desire Modification in Non-human Animals: Circumventing Control, Diminishing Ownership and Undermining Agency.Marc G. Wilcox - 2022 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 35 (3):1-15.
    It is seemingly bad for animals to have their desires modified in at least some cases, for instance where brainwashing or neurological manipulation takes place. In humans, many argue that such modification interferes with our positive liberty or undermines our autonomy but this explanation is inapplicable in the case of animals as they lack the capacity for autonomy in the relevant sense. As such, the standard view has been that, despite any intuitions to the contrary, the modification of animals’ desires (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Consumer demand theory and animal welfare: Value and limitations.Tina Widowski - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):45-45.
  • “Perceived cost” may reveal frustration, but not boredom.Françoise Wemelsfelder - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):44-44.
  • Who suffers?P. D. Wall - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):43-44.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Natural and unnatural justice in animal care.Stephen Walker - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):43-43.
  • The concept of intrinsic value and transgenic animals.H. Verhoog - 1992 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 5 (2):147-160.
    The creation of transgenic animals by means of modern techniques of genetic manipulation is evaluated in the light of different interpretations of the concept of intrinsic value. The zoocentric interpretation, emphasizing the suffering of individual, sentient animals, is described as an extension of the anthropocentric interpretation. In a biocentric or ecocentric approach the concept of intrinsic value first of all denotes independence of humans and a non-instrumental relation to animals. In the zoocentric approach of Bernard Rollin, genetic engineering is seen (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • The Trade-Off Between Chicken Welfare and Public Health Risks in Poultry Husbandry: Significance of Moral Convictions.M. van Asselt, E. D. Ekkel, B. Kemp & E. N. Stassen - 2019 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 32 (2):293-319.
    Welfare-friendly outdoor poultry husbandry systems are associated with potentially higher public health risks for certain hazards, which results in a dilemma: whether to choose a system that improves chicken welfare or a system that reduces these public health risks. We studied the views of citizens and poultry farmers on judging the dilemma, relevant moral convictions and moral arguments in a practical context. By means of an online questionnaire, citizens and poultry farmers judged three practical cases, which illustrate the dilemma of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Concept of Farm Animal Welfare: Citizen Perceptions and Stakeholder Opinion in Flanders, Belgium. [REVIEW]Filiep Vanhonacker, Wim Verbeke, Els Van Poucke, Zuzanna Pieniak, Griet Nijs & Frank Tuyttens - 2012 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 25 (1):79-101.
    Several attempts to conceptualize farm animal welfare have been criticized for diverging reasons, among them often the failure to incorporate the public concern and opinion. This paper’s objective is to develop a conception of farm animal welfare that starts from the public’s perception and integrates the opinion of different stakeholder representatives, thus following a fork-to-farm approach. Four qualitative citizen focus group discussions were used to develop a quantitative questionnaire, which has been completed by a representative sample of Flemish citizens ( (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Paradoxical experimental outcomes and animal suffering.Jaylan Sheila Turkkan - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):42-43.
  • Pain, suffering, and distress.Aubrey Townsend - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):41-42.
  • Broadening the welfare index.Frederick Toates - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):40-41.
  • The attribution of suffering.William Timberlake - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):38-40.
  • Science policy and moral purity: The case of animal biotechnology.Paul B. Thompson - 1997 - Agriculture and Human Values 14 (1):11-27.
    Public controversy over animalbiotechnology is analyzed as a case that illustratestwo broad theoretical approaches for linking science,political or ethical theory, and public policy. Moralpurification proceeds by isolating the social,environmental, animal, and human health impacts ofbiotechnology from each other in terms of discretecategories of moral significance. Each of thesecategories can also be isolated from the sense inwhich biotechnology raises religious or metaphysicalissues. Moral purification yields a comprehensive andsystematic account of normative issues raised bycontroversial science. Hybridization proceeds bytaking concern for all these (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Ethics and the genetic engineering of food animals.Paul B. Thompson - 1997 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 10 (1):1-23.
    Biotechnology applied to traditional foodanimals raises ethical issues in three distinctcategories. First are a series of issues that arise inthe transformation of pigs, sheep, cattle and otherdomesticated farm animals for purposes that deviatesubstantially from food production, including forxenotransplantation or production of pharmaceuticals.Ethical analysis of these issues must draw upon theresources of medical ethics; categorizing them asagricultural biotechnologies is misleading. The secondseries of issues relate to animal welfare. Althoughone can stipulate a number of different philosophicalfoundations for the ethical assessment of welfare,most (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Can the treatment of animals be compared to the holocaust?David Sztybel - 2006 - Ethics and the Environment 11 (1):97-132.
    : The treatment of animals and the Holocaust have been compared many times before, but never has a thoroughly detailed comparison been offered. A thirty-nine-point comparison can be constructed, whether or not one believes that animals are oppressed. The question of whether or not the comparison ought to be expressed merely brings into question whether animal liberationists have liberal-democratic rights to express themselves, which they surely do. Four objections are considered: Is the comparison offensive? Does the comparison trivialize what happened (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Mulesing and Animal Ethics.Joanne Sneddon & Bernard Rollin - 2010 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 23 (4):371-386.
    People for the Ethical Treatment of Animals (PETA) called for a ban on mulesing in the Australian sheep industry in 2004. Mulesing is a surgical procedure that removes wool-bearing skin from the tail and breech area of sheep in order to prevent flystrike (cutaneous myiasis). Flystrike occurs when flies lay their eggs in soiled areas of wool on the sheep and can be fatal for the sheep host. PETA claimed that mulesing subjects sheep to unnecessary pain and suffering and took (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The significance of animal suffering.Peter Singer - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):9-12.
  • The pervasiveness of species bias.Peter Singer - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):759-761.
  • Ethics and animals.Peter Singer - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):45-48.
  • Economic consequences of animal rights programs.James R. Simpson & Bernard E. Rollin - 1984 - Journal of Business Ethics 3 (3):215 - 225.
    Readily available data are used to provide relevant decision making information on the highly subjective issue of animal rights. Two examples of alleged crowding; cattle being finished in concrete lots, and broilers in confined operations were evaluated to determine the impact on producers and consumers from increasing space per animal. It is concluded that similar policy changes, such as doubling floor space, can lead to dramatic differences in economic impact depending on the industry affected. It is shown that economic analysis (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • From one subjectivity to another.S. J. Shettleworth & N. Mrosovsky - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):37-38.
  • Moral Standing of Animals and Some Problems in Veterinarian Ethics.Stefan Sencerz - 2020 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 33 (1):37-48.
    This paper discusses the Indirect Duties View implying that, when our actions have no negative effects on humans, we can treat animals any way we wish. I offer several criticisms of this view. Subsequently, I explore some implications of rejecting this view that rise in the contexts of animal research and veterinarian ethics.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Animal well-being: There are many paths to enlightenment.Evalyn F. Segal - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):36-37.
  • The meaning of speciesism and the forms of animal suffering.S. F. Sapontzis - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):35-36.
  • Emotion, empathy, and suffering.Eric A. Salzen - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):34-35.
  • Assessing animal welfare: Design versus Performance criteria.Jeffrey Rushen - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):758-758.
  • To suffer, or not to suffer? That is the question.Andrew N. Rowan - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):33-34.
  • Science and value.Bernard E. Rollin - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):32-33.
  • Reasonable Partiality and Animal Ethics.Bernard E. Rollin - 2005 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 8 (1-2):105-121.
    Moral psychology is often ignored in ethical theory, making applied ethics difficult to achieve in practice. This is particularly true in the new field of animal ethics. One key feature of moral psychology is recognition of the moral primacy of those with whom we enjoy relationships of love and friendship – philia in Aristotles term. Although a radically new ethic for animal treatment is emerging in society, its full expression is severely limited by our exploitative uses of animals. At this (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Genetic engineering and the sacred.Bernard E. Rollin - 2005 - Zygon 40 (4):939-952.
    Genetic engineering of life forms could well have a profound effect upon our sense of the sacred. Integrating the experience of the sacred as George Bataille does, we can characterize it as a phenomenological encounter with prelinguistic, noncategoreal experience. This view of the sacred is similar to Friedrich Nietzsche's Dionysian experience or Rudolf Otto's mysterium tremendum and diminishes one's sense of self. It seems similar to the eighteenth‐century aesthetic categorization of “the sublime.” Despite the dominant rational approach to religiosity in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ethics and species integrity.Bernard E. Rollin - 2003 - American Journal of Bioethics 3 (3):15 – 17.
  • Suffering as a behaviourist views it.Howard Rachlin - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):32-32.
  • Who can be morally obligated to be a vegetarian?Evelyn Pluhar - 1992 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 5 (2):189-215.
    Kathryn Paxton George has recently argued that vegetarianism cannot be a moral obligation for most human beings, even if Tom Regan is correct in arguing that humans and certain nonhuman animals are equally inherently valuable. She holds that Regan's liberty principle permits humans to kill and eat innocent others who have a right to life, provided that doing so prevents humans from being made worse off. George maintains that obstaining from meat and dairy products would in fact make most humans (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Experimentation on humans and nonhumans.Evelyn B. Pluhar - 2006 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 27 (4):333-355.
    In this article, I argue that it is wrong to conduct any experiment on a nonhuman which we would regard as immoral were it to be conducted on a human, because such experimentation violates the basic moral rights of sentient beings. After distinguishing the rights approach from the utilitarian approach, I delineate basic concepts. I then raise the classic “argument from marginal cases” against those who support experimentation on nonhumans but not on humans. After next replying to six important objections (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Richard P. Haynes: Animal welfare: Competing conceptions and their ethical implication: Springer, London and New York, 2008, 162 pp, ISBN 978-1-4020-8618-2. [REVIEW]Anna Peterson - 2010 - Agriculture and Human Values 27 (4):531-532.
  • Seeking the sources of simian suffering.Melinda A. Novak & Jerrold S. Meyer - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):31-32.
  • The case for and difficulties in using “demand areas” to measure changes in well-being.Yew-Kwang Ng - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):30-31.
  • The ethics and politics of animal welfare in new zealand: Broiler chicken production as a case study. [REVIEW]Michael C. Morris - 2009 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 22 (1):15-30.
    The cause of poor welfare in broilers is multifactorial, but genotype is a major contributor. Modern broilers have been bred for rapid growth, and this leads to increases in lameness and ascites as the legs and hearts of the heavier birds find it difficult to cope with the extra demands placed on them. Visible lameness indicative of pain is more common in New Zealand than in Europe. The government, however, insists that New Zealand welfare standards are higher than Europe. The (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Issues associated with research on sheep parasite control in new zealand – a descriptive ethic.Michael C. Morris - 2003 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 16 (2):187-207.
    In common with much of theEnglish-speaking world, New Zealandersgenerally oppose the use of animalexperimentation where there is no demonstrableand immediate benefit for human, animal, orenvironmental health. Intrusive experiments onsheep internal and external parasites publishedbetween 1996 and 2000 are reviewed, anddiscussed in relation to these publicsensibilities. A total of 16 publishedexperiments on sheep parasites involvedsurgical manipulations or other intrusiveprocedures. Some of these experiments had noshort-term application, or the only applicationwas in increasing animal production. Otherscould have been modified at some extra expenseso (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Consumer demand: Can we deal with differing priorities?P. Monaghan - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):29-30.
  • Development experience and the potential for suffering: Does “out of experience” mean “out of mind”?Michael Mendl - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):28-29.
  • Consumer demand theory and social behavior: All chickens are not equal.Joy A. Mench & W. Ray Stricklin - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):28-28.