Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The Semantics of Entailment.Richard Routley & Robert K. Meyer - 1973 - In Hugues Leblanc (ed.), Truth, Syntax, and Modality: Proceedings Of The Temple University Conference On Alternative Semantlcs. Amsterdam and London: North-Holland Publishing Company. pp. 199-243.
  • Rule Separation and Embedding Theorems for Logics Without Weakening.Clint J. van Alten & James G. Raftery - 2004 - Studia Logica 76 (2):241-274.
    A full separation theorem for the derivable rules of intuitionistic linear logic without bounds, 0 and exponentials is proved. Several structural consequences of this theorem for subreducts of (commutative) residuated lattices are obtained. The theorem is then extended to the logic LR+ and its proof is extended to obtain the finite embeddability property for the class of square increasing residuated lattices.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • The semantics of entailment — III.Richard Routley & Robert K. Meyer - 1972 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 1 (2):192 - 208.
  • Order algebraizable logics.James G. Raftery - 2013 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 164 (3):251-283.
    This paper develops an order-theoretic generalization of Blok and Pigozziʼs notion of an algebraizable logic. Unavoidably, the ordered model class of a logic, when it exists, is not unique. For uniqueness, the definition must be relativized, either syntactically or semantically. In sentential systems, for instance, the order algebraization process may be required to respect a given but arbitrary polarity on the signature. With every deductive filter of an algebra of the pertinent type, the polarity associates a reflexive and transitive relation (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Contextual Deduction Theorems.J. G. Raftery - 2011 - Studia Logica 99 (1-3):279-319.
    Logics that do not have a deduction-detachment theorem (briefly, a DDT) may still possess a contextual DDT —a syntactic notion introduced here for arbitrary deductive systems, along with a local variant. Substructural logics without sentential constants are natural witnesses to these phenomena. In the presence of a contextual DDT, we can still upgrade many weak completeness results to strong ones, e.g., the finite model property implies the strong finite model property. It turns out that a finitary system has a contextual (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Structural Completeness in Substructural Logics.J. S. Olson, J. G. Raftery & C. J. Van Alten - 2008 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 16 (5):453-495.
    Hereditary structural completeness is established for a range of substructural logics, mainly without the weakening rule, including fragments of various relevant or many-valued logics. Also, structural completeness is disproved for a range of systems, settling some previously open questions.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Varieties of de Morgan monoids: Covers of atoms.T. Moraschini, J. G. Raftery & J. J. Wannenburg - 2020 - Review of Symbolic Logic 13 (2):338-374.
    The variety DMM of De Morgan monoids has just four minimal subvarieties. The join-irreducible covers of these atoms in the subvariety lattice of DMM are investigated. One of the two atoms consisting of idempotent algebras has no such cover; the other has just one. The remaining two atoms lack nontrivial idempotent members. They are generated, respectively, by 4-element De Morgan monoids C4 and D4, where C4 is the only nontrivial 0-generated algebra onto which finitely subdirectly irreducible De Morgan monoids may (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Singly generated quasivarieties and residuated structures.Tommaso Moraschini, James G. Raftery & Johann J. Wannenburg - 2020 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 66 (2):150-172.
    A quasivariety of algebras has the joint embedding property (JEP) if and only if it is generated by a single algebra A. It is structurally complete if and only if the free ℵ0‐generated algebra in can serve as A. A consequence of this demand, called ‘passive structural completeness’ (PSC), is that the nontrivial members of all satisfy the same existential positive sentences. We prove that if is PSC then it still has the JEP, and if it has the JEP and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Converse Ackermann croperty and semiclassical negation.José M. Méndez - 1988 - Studia Logica 47 (2):159 - 168.
    A prepositional logic S has the Converse Ackermann Property (CAP) if (AB)C is unprovable in S when C does not contain . In A Routley-Meyer semantics for Converse Ackermann Property (Journal of Philosophical Logic, 16 (1987), pp. 65–76) I showed how to derive positive logical systems with the CAP. There I conjectured that each of these positive systems were compatible with a so-called semiclassical negation. In the present paper I prove that this conjecture was right. Relational Routley-Meyer type semantics are (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • New axiomatics for relevant logics, I.Robert K. Meyer - 1974 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 3 (1/2):53 - 86.
  • E is a conservative extension of eī.Robert K. Meyer & Richard Routley - 1974 - Philosophia 4 (2-3):223-249.
  • Conservative extension in relevant implication.Robert K. Meyer - 1973 - Studia Logica 31 (1):39 - 48.
  • Conservative Extension in Relevant Arithmetic.Robert K. Meyer & Igor Urbas - 1986 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 32 (1‐5):45-50.
  • Fragments of R-Mingle.W. J. Blok & J. G. Raftery - 2004 - Studia Logica 78 (1-2):59-106.
    The logic RM and its basic fragments (always with implication) are considered here as entire consequence relations, rather than as sets of theorems. A new observation made here is that the disjunction of RM is definable in terms of its other positive propositional connectives, unlike that of R. The basic fragments of RM therefore fall naturally into two classes, according to whether disjunction is or is not definable. In the equivalent quasivariety semantics of these fragments, which consist of subreducts of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Idealist Origins: 1920s and Before.Martin Davies & Stein Helgeby - 2014 - In Graham Oppy & Nick Trakakis (eds.), History of Philosophy in Australia and New Zealand. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Springer. pp. 15-54.
    This paper explores early Australasian philosophy in some detail. Two approaches have dominated Western philosophy in Australia: idealism and materialism. Idealism was prevalent between the 1880s and the 1930s, but dissipated thereafter. Idealism in Australia often reflected Kantian themes, but it also reflected the revival of interest in Hegel through the work of ‘absolute idealists’ such as T. H. Green, F. H. Bradley, and Henry Jones. A number of the early New Zealand philosophers were also educated in the idealist tradition (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark