Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Max Frischeisen-Köhler’s Vindication of the Material Component of Cognition.Andrea Staiti - 2016 - Philosophia Scientiae 20:119-142.
    Cet article présente la philosophie des sciences de Max Frischeisen-Köhler, conçue comme une réponse critique aux néo-kantiens. Frischeisen-Köhler tire son enseignement à la fois de son professeur Wilhelm Dilthey et d’Edmund Husserl. Dans les quatre premières parties j’examine la critique que Frischeisen-Köhler adresse au néo-kantisme de l’École de Marbourg et à celui de l’École de Baden. Cette critique défend l’idée que la réalité joue un rôle dans la cognition en tant qu’élément totalement indépendant que la cognition doit reconnaître et qui (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Husserl and Rickert on the Nature of Judgment.Andrea Staiti - 2015 - Philosophy Compass 10 (12):815-827.
    In this paper I present and assess a controversy between Edmund Husserl and Heinrich Rickert on the nature of judgment, in order to bring to light the originality of Husserl's proposal concerning this important issue. In the first section I provide some context for Rickert's theory of judgment by sketching a reconstruction of nineteenth century logical theory and then proceed to introduce Rickert's view. I suggest that nineteenth century logic is characterized by a criticism of the traditional view that sees (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Space as Form of Intuition and as Formal Intuition: On the Note to B160 in Kant's Critique of Pure Reason.Christian Onof & Dennis Schulting - 2015 - Philosophical Review 124 (1):1-58.
    In his argument for the possibility of knowledge of spatial objects, in the Transcendental Deduction of the B-version of the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant makes a crucial distinction between space as “form of intuition” and space as “formal intuition.” The traditional interpretation regards the distinction between the two notions as reflecting a distinction between indeterminate space and determinations of space by the understanding, respectively. By contrast, a recent influential reading has argued that the two notions can be fused into (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Historia y normatividad. El problema de su articulación en el Neokantismo de Baden.Jacinto Páez Bonifaci - 2022 - Ideas Y Valores 71 (178):97-115.
    El presente trabajo intenta ofrecer una interpretación general de la filosofía de la historia en el neokantismo de Baden. La interpretación tradicional afirma que la filosofía de la historia neokantiana es una variante de la llamada filosofía crítica de la historia y que el interés de los neokantianos por la historia se origina en las polémicas decimonónicas en torno al método de las humanidades. Nuestra tesis, por el contrario, es que tal filosofía tiene su origen en problemas internos a la (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Between history and system. Heinrich Rickert’s concept of culture.Giovanni Morrone - 2022 - Filozofija I Društvo 33 (2):349-369.
    The paper reconstructs the concept of culture that emerges from Heinrich Rickert?s neo-Kantianism, uncovering its major historical-problematic, methodological, and philosophical implications. The central theme of the first section is the idea that modern culture is uniquely characterized by?fragmentation?. It also unpacks the programme of Rickert?s philosophy of culture, which pursues the task of reconstructing the lost unity of culture. The second section explains the methodological implications of the problematic relationship between value and reality established in cultural goods and evaluations. Finally, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Rickert en France (1890-1940).Guillemette Leblanc - 2023 - Les Cahiers Philosophiques de Strasbourg 54:179-205.
    La réception française d’Heinrich Rickert (1863-1936), au début du xxe siècle, s’inscrit tout d’abord au cœur des débats épistémologiques autour de la constitution des sciences historiques et des sciences sociales, ainsi que l’atteste la controverse entre Paul Lacombe et Alexandru Dimitri Xenopol. Le second volet de la réception de Rickert en France concerne la philosophie des valeurs et le lien qu’elle entretient avec les positions épistémologiques défendues par le néokantien de Bade. L’étude de cet aspect de la réception se fera (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Le problème de la fondation de l'ontologie sociale et les dispositifs fondationnels du néokantisme de Bade.Christian Krijnen - 2010 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 92 (1):67.
    Résumé — Bien que le « social » ne soit pas un thème central du néokantisme de Bade, il est néanmoins l’occasion de développer, dans le contexte de ce courant philosophique, ce qu’on appelle aujourd’hui une ontologie sociale, qui peut être élaborée de manière exemplaire dans la perspective de Rickert. La conception fondamentale de la philosophie de l’histoire, que j’analyse, offre chez Rickert la clef d’une détermination formelle de l’ontologie sociale. En outre, Rickert offre une base systématique qui permet de (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Le sens de l’être. Heidegger et le néokantisme.Christian Krijnen - 2003 - Methodos 3.
    Le néokantisme – souvent critiqué de façon polémique par Heidegger et ses disciples –, en particulier le néokantisme de son maître, Heinrich Rickert, présente une théorie de la compréhension humaine plus approfondie que celle de Heidegger. D’une part, Heidegger est replacé dans son temps, puis les principes de la théorie de Rickert sur le sens et les valeurs sont esquissés. D’autre part, un problème de base de la phénoménologie est analysé ; il apparaît en fin de compte que la validité (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Culture and freedom in transcendental and speculative idealism.Christian Krijnen - 2022 - Filozofija I Društvo 33 (2):407-419.
    The founding fathers of modern philosophy of culture, the neo-Kantians, and especially the Southwest school, brought the concept of culture into play as a counter concept to that of nature. Taking Heinrich Rickert?s conception of culture as a starting point, the article shows how culture is conceived of as a self-formation of the subject. It leads to transcendental idealism of freedom, typical of a Kantian type of transcendental philosophy. However, in this self and world formation of the subject it is (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Vertybių ir vertinimo problema heideggerio filosofijoje.Dalius Jonkus - 2017 - Problemos 91:87.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • El programa fenomenológico y la construcción husserliana de los adversarios en “La filosofía como ciencia estricta”.Hernán Inverso - 2019 - Ideas Y Valores 68 (171):251-277.
    Husserl se esforzó por desarrollar vías de abordaje a la fenomenología que facilitaran su expansión. En “La filosofía como ciencia estricta” traza un diagnóstico de los obstáculos en el entramado de naturalismo e historicismo, y estudia su lógica deconstrucción a través de tres tópicos: apelación al psicologismo como elemento del naturalismo, interpretación de Hume como protofenomenólogo y lectura historicista de Dilthey. Esto permitirá observar datos relevantes sobre el modo como Husserl concibe en este período la especificidad y alcances de la (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Searching for the Self: Early Phenomenological Accounts of Self-Consciousness from Lotze to Scheler.Guillaume Frechette - 2013 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 21 (5):1-26.
    Phenomenological accounts of self-consciousness are often said to combine two elements by means of a necessary connection: the primitive and irre- ducible subjective character of experiences and the idealist transcendental constitution of consciousness. In what follows I argue that this connection is not necessary in order for an account of self-consciousness to be phenomenological, as shown by early phenomenological accounts of self- consciousness – particularly in Munich phenomenology. First of all, I show that the account of self-consciousness defended by these (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Kantian origins of Sergei Rubinstein's theory of moral improvement.Nina A. Dmitrieva - 2021 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 55 (6):1126-1141.
    Journal of Philosophy of Education, EarlyView.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • La critique néokantienne de Kant et l’instauration d’une théorie conceptualiste de la perception.Arnaud Dewalque - 2010 - Dialogue 49 (3):413-433.
    ABSTRACT : This paper contributes to explor the historical background of contemporary conceptualism. It suggests that a step forward toward a more promising understanding of this historical background can be made if we focus, not on the much-discussed, controversial position of Kant, but rather on the straightforward position of some main representatives of classical neo-Kantianism. My main hypothesis is that criticisms of Kant’s transcendantal aesthetics coming from Paul Natorp and Bruno Bauch may be regarded as a significant historical source for (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Ernst Cassirer on historical thought and the demarcation problem of epistemology.Francesca Biagioli - 2021 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 29 (4):652-670.
    Cassirer’s neo-Kantian epistemology has become a classical reference in contemporary history and philosophy of science. However, the historical aspects of his thought are sometimes seen to be in some tension with his defence of a priori elements of knowledge. This paper reconsiders Cassirer’s strategy to address this tension by positing functional dependencies at the core of the notion of objectivity. This requires the epistemologist to account for the determination of the objects of knowledge within given scientific theories, but also for (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation