Switch to: References

Citations of:

James J. Gibson And The Psychology Of Perception

New Haven: Yale University Press (1988)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Direct perception in context: radical empiricist reflections on the medium.Ludger van Dijk & Julian Kiverstein - 2020 - Synthese 198 (9):8389-8411.
    Radical empiricists at the turn of the twentieth century described organisms as experiencing the relations they maintain with their surroundings prior to any analytic separation from their environment. They notably avoided separating perception of the material environment from social life. This perspective on perceptual experience was to prove the inspiration for Gibson’s ecological approach to perceptual psychology. Gibson provided a theory of how the direct perception of the organism-environment relation is possible. Central to his account was the notion of a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Review article.[author unknown] - 1994 - Semiotica 99 (3-4):319-440.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Environments of Intelligence. From Natural Information to Artficial Interaction.Hajo Greif - 2017 - London: Routledge.
    What is the role of the environment, and of the information it provides, in cognition? More specifically, may there be a role for certain artefacts to play in this context? These are questions that motivate "4E" theories of cognition (as being embodied, embedded, extended, enactive). In his take on that family of views, Hajo Greif first defends and refines a concept of information as primarily natural, environmentally embedded in character, which had been eclipsed by information-processing views of cognition. He continues (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mind reading, pretence and imitation in monkeys and apes.A. Whiten - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):170-171.
  • Fixations or smooth eye movements?Alexander H. Wertheim - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):281-282.
  • Is lack of understanding of cause-effect relationships a suitable basis for interpreting monkeys' failures in attribution?Elisabetta Visalberghi - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):169-170.
  • Football, Culture, Skill Development and Sport Coaching: Extending Ecological Approaches in Athlete Development Using the Skilled Intentionality Framework.James Vaughan, Clifford J. Mallett, Paul Potrac, Maurici A. López-Felip & Keith Davids - 2021 - Frontiers in Psychology 12.
    In this manuscript, we extend ecological approaches and suggest ideas for enhancing athlete development by utilizing the Skilled Intentionality Framework. A broad aim is to illustrate the extent to which social, cultural and historical aspects of life are embodied in the way football is played and the skills young footballers develop during learning. Here, we contend that certain aspects of the world are “weighted” with social and cultural significance, “standing out” to be more readily perceived and simultaneously acted upon when (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Visual stability: What is new?P. van Donkelaar & U. Windhorst - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):280-281.
  • Reasons for pragmatism: affording epistemic contact in a shared environment.Ludger van Dijk & Erik Myin - 2019 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 18 (5):973-997.
    Theorizing about perception is often motivated by a belief that without a way of ensuring that our perceptual experience correctly reflects the external world we cannot be sure that we perceive the world at all. Historically, coming up with a way of securing such epistemic contact has been a foundational issue in psychology. Recent ecological and enactive approaches challenge the requirement for perception to attain epistemic contact. This article aims to explicate this pragmatic starting point and the new direction of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • What does calibration solve?Arnold Trehub - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):279-280.
  • Cognitive ethology comes of age.Michael Tomasello - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):168-169.
  • There is no “point” to space.Gary W. Strong - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):279-279.
  • The translation solution plus motion suppression account for perceived stability.Arnold E. Stoper - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):278-279.
  • Mutualism in the human sciences: Towards the implementation of a theory.Arthur Still & James M. M. Good - 1992 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 22 (2):105–128.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The meaning of meaning in biology and cognitive science.Göran Sonesson - 2006 - Sign Systems Studies 34 (1):135-211.
    The present essay aims at integrating different concepts of meaning developed in semiotics, biology, and cognitive science, in a way that permits the formulation of issues involving evolution and development. The concept of sign in semiotics, just like the notion of representation in cognitive science, have either been used too broadly, or outright rejected. My earlier work on the notions of iconicity and pictoriality has forced me to spell out the taken-forgranted meaning of the sign concept, both in the Saussurean (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Prolegomena to the semiotic analysis of prehistoric visual displays.Göran Sonesson - 1994 - Semiotica 100 (2-4):267-332.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Vector code in space constancy.E. N. Sokolov - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):278-278.
  • The sounds of silence.Charles T. Snowdon - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):167-168.
  • Stability relative to what?Jeroen B. J. Smeets & Eli Brenner - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):277-278.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Calibration models and ecological efference mediation theory: Toward a synthesis of indirect and direct perception theories.Wayne L. Shebilske - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):276-277.
  • Conventional naturalism: A perceptualist account of pictorial representation.Sonia Sedivy - 1996 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 10 (2):103-125.
    This paper proposes that pictures are functional objects which figure in norm‐governed practices of usage yet whose specific function is to present the world as it looks to acculturated perceivers. Pictorial content presents the way the world looks to a subject's acculturated perceptual grasp. Hence, pictorial content needs to be explained in terms of a theory of perceptual content, but a novel theory which departs from the two‐stage sensation‐based approach to perception and the polarization between naturalism and conventionalism that it (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Knowing thyself, knowing the other: They're not the same.Jonathan Schull & J. David Smith - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):166-167.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Against methodological solipsism: The ecological approach.Mark Rowlands - 1995 - Philosophical Psychology 8 (1):5-24.
    This paper argues that an ecological approach to psychology of the sort advanced by J. J. Gibson provides a coherent and powerful alternative to the computational, information-processing, paradigm. The paper argues for two principles. Firstly, one cannot begin to understand what internal information processing an organism must accomplish until one understands what information is available to the organism in its environment. Secondly, an organism can process information by acting on or manipulating physical structures in its environment. An attempt is made (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • On the locus of visual stability.Daniel N. Robinson - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):275-276.
  • How do monkeys remember the world?R. M. Ridley - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):166-166.
  • Theory, concept, and experiment in the history of psychology: the older tradition behind a 'young science'.Edward S. Reed - 1989 - History of the Human Sciences 2 (3):333-356.
  • Knowers talking about the known: Ecological realism as a philosophy of science.Edward S. Reed - 1992 - Synthese 92 (1):9-23.
  • A Theory of Resonance: Towards an Ecological Cognitive Architecture.Vicente Raja - 2018 - Minds and Machines 28 (1):29-51.
    This paper presents a blueprint for an ecological cognitive architecture. Ecological psychology, I contend, must be complemented with a story about the role of the CNS in perception, action, and cognition. To arrive at such a story while staying true to the tenets of ecological psychology, it will be necessary to flesh out the central metaphor according to which the animal perceives its environment by ‘resonating’ to information in energy patterns: what is needed is a theory of resonance. I offer (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • The “enhanced” warrior: drone warfare and the problematics of separation.Danial Qaurooni & Hamid Ekbia - 2017 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 16 (1):53-73.
    Unmanned Aerial Vehicles, or drones, are increasingly employed for military purposes. They are extolled for improving operational endurance and targeting precision on the one hand and keeping drone crew from harm on the other. In the midst of such praise, what falls by the wayside is an entangled set of concerns about the ways in which the relationship between the pilots and their operational environment is being reconfigured. This paper traces the various manifestations of this reconfiguration and goes on to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Neuronal death of the cancellation theory?Claude Prablanc - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):274-275.
    The question of how the brain can construct a stable representation of the external world despite eye movements is a very old one. If there have been some wrong statements of problems (such as the inverted retinal image), other statements are less naive and have led to analytic solutions possibly adopted by the brain to counteract the spurious effects of eye movements. Following the MacKay (1973) objections to the analytic view of perceptual stability, Bridgeman et al. claim that the idea (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On attributing mental states to monkeys: First, know thyself.Daniel J. Povinelli & Sandra deBlois - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):164-166.
  • Is perception isomorphic with neural activity?Alexandre Pouget & Terrence J. Sejnowski - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):274-274.
  • Enactivism and Ecological Psychology: The Role of Bodily Experience in Agency.Yanna B. Popova & Joanna Rączaszek-Leonardi - 2020 - Frontiers in Psychology 11:539841.
    This paper considers some foundational concepts in ecological psychology and in enactivism., and traces their developments from their historical roots to current preoccupations. Important differences stem, we claim, from dissimilarities in how embodied experience has been understood by the ancestors, founders and followers of ecological psychology and enactivism, respectively. Rather than pointing to differences in domains of interest for the respective approaches, and restating possible divisions of labor between them in research in the cognitive and psychological sciences, we call for (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The “calibration” solution still leaves much work to be done.A. P. Petrov - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):273-274.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Exploring the “boundary” between the minds of monkeys and humans.Sidney I. Perloe - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):163-164.
  • The perceptual stability of the visual field: What is calibration for?Jacques Paillard, Michelle Fleury, Normand Teasdale, Chantal Bard & Vincent Nougier - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):272-272.
  • Calls as labels: An intriguing theme, but one with limitations.Donald H. Owings - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):162-163.
  • Seeing where we look: Fixation as extraretinal information.D. Alfred Owens & Edward S. Reed - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):271-272.
  • The world as an outside iconic memory – no strong internal metric means no problem of visual stability.J. Kevin O'Regan - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):270-271.
  • What are mental states?William Noble & Iain Davidson - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):162-162.
  • Why do things look as they do? Some Gibsonian answers to koffka's question.Thomas Natsoulas - 1991 - Philosophical Psychology 4 (2):183-202.
  • Reasons for pragmatism: affording epistemic contact in a shared environment.Erik Myin & Ludger Dijk - 2019 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 18 (5):973-997.
    Theorizing about perception is often motivated by a belief that without a way of ensuring that our perceptual experience correctly reflects the external world we cannot be sure that we perceive the world at all. Historically, coming up with a way of securing such epistemic contact has been a foundational issue in psychology. Recent ecological and enactive approaches challenge the requirement for perception to attain epistemic contact. This article aims to explicate this pragmatic starting point and the new direction of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Theory of coordinate transformation by efference copy survives another attack.H. Mittelstaedt - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):269-270.
  • Are monkeys nomothetic or idiographic?Linda Mealey - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):161-161.
  • Is there any essential difference between the “calibration” and “elimination” solutions?S. Mateeff & J. Hohnsbein - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):268-269.
  • Architectural Values, Political Affordances and Selective Permeability.Crippen Mathew & Klement Vladan - 2020 - Open Philosophy 3 (1):462-477.
    This article connects value-sensitive design to Gibson’s affordance theory: the view that we perceive in terms of the ease or difficulty with which we can negotiate space. Gibson’s ideas offer a nonsubjectivist way of grasping culturally relative values, out of which we develop a concept of political affordances, here understood as openings or closures for social action, often implicit. Political affordances are equally about environments and capacities to act in them. Capacities and hence the severity of affordances vary with age, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The History and Philosophy of Ecological Psychology.Lorena Lobo, Manuel Heras-Escribano & David Travieso - 2018 - Frontiers in Psychology 9.
  • Task dependent spatial memory across saccades.Keith S. Karn, Joel Lachter, Per Møller & Mary Hayhoe - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):267-268.
  • Visual stability and transsaccadic information processing.Martin Jüttner - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):266-267.
  • A localist evaluation solution for visual stability across saccades.David E. Irwin, George W. McConkie, Laura A. Carlson-Radvansky & Christopher Currie - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):265-266.