Switch to: References

Citations of:

The concept of a legal system

Oxford,: Clarendon Press (1970)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Concretized Norm and Sanction qua_ Fact in the Vienna School's _Stufenbaulehre.Martin Borowski - 2014 - Ratio Juris 27 (1):79-93.
    At the bottom level of the hierarchical structure (Stufenbau) of the legal system, the transition from “ought” to “is” has not been given its due. I argue that an additional level, that of fully concretized norms, belongs in the hierarchy. This sheds light on precisely where and how the transition from “ought” to “is” takes place. Whereas the fully concretized norm marks the bottom level in the hierarchy of norms, the coercive act or sanction qua fact is not found in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Lost in the System or Lost in Translation? The Exchanges between Hart and Ross.Svein Eng - 2011 - Ratio Juris 24 (2):194-246.
    According to the received opinion there is a theoretical incompatibility between Herbert Hart'sThe Concept of Lawand Alf Ross'sOn Law and Justice, and, according to the received opinion, it stems above all from Hart's emphasis on the internal point of view. The present paper argues that this reading is mistaken.The Concept of Lawdoes not go beyondOn Law and Justicein so far as both present arguments to the effect that law is based on a shared understanding between participants in a project perceived (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Idealism, Empiricism, Pluralism, Law: Legal truth after modernity.Luke Mason - forthcoming - In Angela Condello & Tiziana Andina (eds.), Post-Truth, Law and Philosophy. Routledge.
    Making a connection between ‘post-modernism’ and post-truth has by now become a standard trope, both within academia and popular discourse, despite post-truth’s only recent emergence as a concept. Such claims are often rather vague and fanciful and lack an altogether credible account of either phenomenon in many cases. This Chapter argues however that within a legal context, there is the emergence of a legal post-truth which is the direct consequence of a concrete form of post-modernity within legal practice and thought. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Legal Indeterminacy and Constitutional Interpretation.José Juan Moreso - 1998 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer.
    In this book, I present the results of an investigation which began with an extended stay at Oxford's Balliol College during the first half of 1995. My visit to Oxford was made possible by a grant from the Spanish Ministerio de Educaci6n y Ciencia. My sincere thanks go to Joseph Raz who served as my supervisor in Oxford. For several points of the present study, conversations with Timothy Endicott in Oxford were also of great help. The book is part of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Vertical precedents in formal models of precedential constraint.Gabriel L. Broughton - 2019 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 27 (3):253-307.
    The standard model of precedential constraint holds that a court is equally free to modify a precedent of its own and a precedent of a superior court—overruling aside, it does not differentiate horizontal and vertical precedents. This paper shows that no model can capture the U.S. doctrine of precedent without making that distinction. A precise model is then developed that does just that. This requires situating precedent cases in a formal representation of a hierarchical legal structure, and adjusting the constraint (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Beyond Legal Minds: Sex, Social Violence, Systems, Methods, Possibilities.William Allen Brant (ed.) - 2019 - Boston: Brill | Rodopi.
    In this book, William Brant inquires how violence is reduced. Social causes of violence are exposed. War, sexual domination, leadership, propagandizing and comedy are investigated. Legal systems are explored as reducers and implementers of violence and threats.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • War crimes and expressive theories of punishment: Communication or denunciation?Bill Wringe - 2010 - Res Publica 16 (2):119-133.
    In a paper published in 2006, I argued that the best way of defending something like our current practices of punishing war criminals would be to base the justification of this practice on an expressive theory of punishment. I considered two forms that such a justification could take—a ‘denunciatory’ account, on which the purpose of punishment is supposed to communicate a commitment to certain kinds of standard to individuals other than the criminal and a ‘communicative’ account, on which the purpose (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Rules, Principles, Algorithms and the Description of Legal Systems.Stephen Utz - 1992 - Ratio Juris 5 (1):23-45.
    Abstract.Although the Hart/Dworkin debate has as much to do with Dworkin's affirmative theory of judicial discretion as with Hart's more comprehensive theory of law, the starting point was of course Dworkin's attempt to demolish the “model of rules,” Hart's alleged analysis of legal systems as collections of conclusive reasons for specified legal consequences. The continuing relevance of this attack for the prospects for any theory of law is the subject of the present essay.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • What Is Legal Philosophy?Sebastián Urbina - 2005 - Ratio Juris 18 (2):144-161.
    . This paper argues that legal philosophy is a social practice undertaken by participants whose views have primacy over non‐participants. This social practice is dynamic, constructive and based on understanding and explanation, in order to meet normative expectations. Legal Philosophy should include Legal Ontology, Legal Epistemology and a Theory of Justice. It is usually claimed that legal philosophy is a branch of a genus called philosophy, but there is no one single definition of it. In this paper it is argued (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Teoría general Del derecho.William Twining - 2005 - Anales de la Cátedra Francisco Suárez 39:597-688.
    This paper sets out a view of a General Jurisprudence that is needed to underpin the institutionalised discipline of law as it becomes more cosmopolitan in the context of “globalisation”, and considers its implications. Part I restates a position on the mission and nature of the discipline of law and of the role of jurisprudence, as its theoretical part, in contributing to the health of the discipline. Part II clarifies some questions that have been raised about this conception of General (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Intelligibility of Extralegal State Action: A General Lesson for Debates on Public Emergencies and Legality.François Tanguay-Renaud - 2010 - Legal Theory 16 (3):161-189.
    Some legal theorists deny that states can conceivably act extra-legally, in the sense of acting contrary to domestic law. This position finds its most robust articulation in the writings of Hans Kelsen, and has more recently been taken up by David Dyzenhaus in the context of his work on emergencies and legality. This paper seeks to demystify their arguments and, ultimately, contend that we can intelligibly speak of the state as a legal wrongdoer or a legally unauthorized actor.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Lost in the System or Lost in Translation? The Exchanges between Hart and Ross.E. N. G. Svein - 2011 - Ratio Juris 24 (2):194-246.
    According to the received opinion there is a theoretical incompatibility between Herbert Hart's The Concept of Law and Alf Ross's On Law and Justice, and, according to the received opinion, it stems above all from Hart's emphasis on the internal point of view. The present paper argues that this reading is mistaken. The Concept of Law does not go beyond On Law and Justice in so far as both present arguments to the effect that law is based on a shared (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • What Is “Law,” if “the Law” Is not Something that “Is”? A Modest Contribution to a Major Question.Dan Jerker B. Svantesson - 2013 - Ratio Juris 26 (3):456-485.
    After proposing an alternative definition of what “law” (jurisprudential concept) is, this article demonstrates the impossibility of identifying “the law” (what law-makers announce, relative to a particular jurisdiction) as something that is in a particular way. Rather, the law is a more or less abstract range of options. Drawing upon this conclusion, the article calls for a reassessment of how we view the role of law-makers. We need to remove the mystery that surrounds the law so as to provide for (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Norms that Confer Competence.Torben Spaak - 2003 - Ratio Juris 16 (1):89-104.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Legal Positivism, Law's Normativity, and the Normative Force of Legal Justification.Torben Spaak - 2003 - Ratio Juris 16 (4):469-485.
    In this article, I distinguish between a moral and a strictly legal conception of legal normativity, and argue that legal positivists can account for law's normativity in the strictly legal but not in the moral sense, while pointing out that normativity in the former sense is of little interest, at least to lawyers. I add, however, that while the moral conception of law's normativity is to be preferred to the strictly legal conception from the rather narrow viewpoint of the study (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Karl Olivecrona's Legal Philosophy. A Critical Appraisal.Torben Spaak - 2011 - Ratio Juris 24 (2):156-193.
    I argue in this article (i) that Karl Olivecrona's legal philosophy, especially the critique of the view that law has binding force, the analysis of the concept and function of a legal rule, and the idea that law is a matter of organized force, is a significant contribution to twentieth century legal philosophy. I also argue (ii) that Olivecrona fails to substantiate some of his most important empirical claims, and (iii) that the distinction espoused by Olivecrona between the truth and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Legal System and Practical Reason. On the Structure of a Normative Theory of Law.Jan-Reinard Sieckmann - 1992 - Ratio Juris 5 (3):288-307.
    It will be argued, firstly, that there is a link between the legal validity of a norm and the rational justifiability of a requirement that judges should apply this norm, based on a normative conception of legal validity and the postulate that judges should act as rational persons; secondly, that rational justifiability of legal norms requires the construction of a legal system in a model of principles that differs from theories, e.g., of Kelsen, Hart, Dworkin and Alexy, which are not (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Sources of Law Are not Legal Norms.Fábio Perin Shecaira - 2015 - Ratio Juris 28 (1):15-30.
    Anglo-American authors have paid little attention to a subtle distinction that has important jurisprudential implications. It is the distinction between sources of law and the legal norms which can be derived from sources by means of interpretation. The distinction might also be rendered as a threefold one, separating sources of law from legal norms and both of these from that which mediates their relation, namely, methods of legal interpretation. This paper intends to state the “source-norm” distinction clearly and to give (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Was Austin right after all? On the role of sanctions in a theory of law.Frederick Schauer - 2010 - Ratio Juris 23 (1):1-21.
    In modern jurisprudence it is taken as axiomatic that John Austin's sanction-based account of law and legal obligation was demolished in H.L.A. Hart's The Concept of Law, but Hart's victory and the deficiencies of the Austinian account may not be so clear. Not only does the alleged linguistic distinction between being obliged and having an obligation fail to provide as much support for the idea of a sanction-independent legal obligation as is commonly thought, but the soundness of Hart's claims, as (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Legalist Fictions and the Problem of Scientific Legitimation.Jiří Přibáň - 2003 - Ratio Juris 16 (1):14-36.
    The author analyzes fictions of legal positivist philosophy and their role in the scientific legitimation of modern law and political domination. The original function of legalist fictions was the establishment of legal science, which would be autonomous and independent of other social sciences and public morality. In the second half of the 20th century, legal positivist philosophy has nevertheless adopted the fiction of the just law as its scientific legitimation fiction and incorporated moral and political discourse into legal science, again.Legal (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Melody and Law's Mindfulness of Time.Gerald J. Postema - 2004 - Ratio Juris 17 (2):203-226.
    . A structured awareness of time lies at the core of the law's distinctive normativity. Melody is offered as a rough model of this mindfulness of time, since some important features of this awareness are also present in a hearer's grasp of melody. The model of melody is used, first, to identify some temporal dimensions of intentional action and then to highlight law's mindfulness of time. Its role in the structure of legal thinking, and especially in precedent‐sensitive legal reasoning, is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Law, Morality, Coherence and Truth.Aleksander Peczenik - 1994 - Ratio Juris 7 (2):146-176.
    The author analyzes the relations between truth and law starting from the distinction between practical and theoretical spheres. He shows, first, how moral and legal statements and reasoning are connected with an operation of weighing and balancing different values and principles and how this operation is ultimately based on personal and intuitive preferences and feeling. The criteria developed by the theoretical sciences to define truth (coherence, consensus and pragmatic success) can only be translated into practical statements as criteria of correctness (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Continental Normativism and Its British Counterpart: How Different Are They?Stanley L. Paulson - 1993 - Ratio Juris 6 (3):227-244.
    The separability thesis claims that the concept of law can be explicated independently of morality, the normativity thesis, that it can be explicated independently of fact. Continental normativism, prominent above all in the work of Hans Kelsen, may be characterized in terms of the coupling of these theses. Like Kelsen, H. L. A. Hart is a proponent of the separability thesis. And–a leitmotiv–both theorists reject reductive legal positivism. They do not, however, reject it for the same reasons. Kelsen's reason, in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • An Empowerment Theory of Legal Norms.Stanley L. Paulson - 1988 - Ratio Juris 1 (1):58-72.
    Traditionally legal theorists, whenever engaged in controversy, have agreed on one point: legal norms are par excellence rules which impose obligations. The author examines this assumption, which from another perspective (that of constitutional law, for instance) appears less obvious. In fact, constitutional rules are commoniy empowering norms, norms which do not create duties but powers. To this objection many theorists would reply that empowering rules are incomplete and that they are to be understood as parts of duty‐creating rules. A different (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • No More Fresh Starts. [REVIEW]M. C. Murphy - 2012 - Analysis 72 (3):563-573.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Some Remarks on the Notions of Legal Order and Legal System.José Juan Moreso & Pablo Eugenio Navarro - 1993 - Ratio Juris 6 (1):48-63.
  • The Various Relations between Law and Morality in Contemporary Legal Philosophy.Michael S. Moore - 2012 - Ratio Juris 25 (4):435-471.
    This paper is intended to be a summary of the author's views on the relationship between law and morality worked out over the past three decades in jurisprudence. The paper preliminarily clarifies the matter by isolating some lines of cleavage separating different questions askable about this relationship. With this done, the author argues for two theses. One, that judges are obligated to use morality in their decisions in particular cases; and two, that the morality judges are obligated to use in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Sovereignty and International Order.Thomas May - 1995 - Ratio Juris 8 (3):287-295.
  • Double Pairs.Rafael Hernandez Marfn - 1993 - Ratio Juris 6 (3):305-323.
    This article discusses C. E. Alchourrdn and E. Bulygin's ideas regarding the distinction between strong permission and weak permission. The author takes for granted that the distinction between the two terms should be placed at the level of the assertive metalanguage about norms. But the symbolizations and the definitions of strong and weak permissions offered by Alchourrdn and Bulygin, as well as their thesis concerning the relations between the two concepts are challenged.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Self-determination, non-domination, and federalism.Jacob T. Levy - 2008 - Hypatia 23 (3):pp. 60-78.
    This article summarizes the theory of federalism as non-domination Iris Marion Young began to develop in her final years, a theory of self-government that tried to recognize interconnectedness. Levy also poses an objection to that theory: non-domination cannot do the work Young needed of it, because it is a theory about the merits of decisions not about jurisdiction over them. The article concludes with an attempt to give Young the last word.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Self-determination, Non-domination, and Federalism.Jacob T. Levy - 2008 - Hypatia 23 (3):60-78.
    This article summarizes the theory of federalism as non-domination Iris Marion Young began to develop in her final years, a theory of self-government that tried to recognize interconnectedness. Levy also poses an objection to that theory: non-domination cannot do the work Young needed of it, because it is a theory about the merits of decisions not about jurisdiction over them. The article concludes with an attempt to give Young the last word.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Kelsen's Pallid Normativity.James W. Harris - 1996 - Ratio Juris 9 (1):94-117.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Patterns for legal compliance checking in a decidable framework of linked open data.Enrico Francesconi & Guido Governatori - 2022 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 31 (3):445-464.
    This paper presents an approach for legal compliance checking in the Semantic Web which can be effectively applied for applications in the Linked Open Data environment. It is based on modeling deontic norms in terms of ontology classes and ontology property restrictions. It is also shown how this approach can handle norm defeasibility. Such methodology is implemented by decidable fragments of OWL 2, while legal reasoning is carried out by available decidable reasoners. The approach is generalised by presenting patterns for (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A description logic framework for advanced accessing and reasoning over normative provisions.Enrico Francesconi - 2014 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 22 (3):291-311.
    A model of normative provisions and related axioms represented by using RDF/owl are presented as a contribution to implement the semantic web in the legal domain. In particular, a pattern able to implement the Hohfeldian legal fundamental relations between provisions using OWL-DL expressivity is proposed. Moreover, a query-based approach able to deal with relations between provision instances is described. An example of advanced access and reasoning over provisions using the proposed approach, as well as a prototype architecture of a provision (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • A Pragma-Dialectical Approach to Legal Discussions.Eveline T. Feteris - 1993 - Informal Logic 15 (3).
  • Sistema e struttura nel diritto.Carla Faralli - 2004 - Ratio Juris 17 (2):259-262.
    Book reviewed:Mario G. Losano, Sistema e struttura nel diritto.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Legal Positivism as a Theory of Law’s Existence.Jorge Luis Fabra-Zamora - 2022 - Isonomía. Revista de Teoría y Filosofía Del Derecho 55.
    El positivismo jurídico como teoría sobre la existencia del derecho: un comentario sobre Judging Positivism de Margaret Martin Este comentario examina de forma crítica la concepción de positivismo jurídico que informa el desafío planteado por Margaret Martin contra la substancia y el método de esta tradición intelectual. La afirmación central de este artículo es que su caracterización de la teoría substantiva del positivismo jurídico deja de lado una dimensión más fundamental, y explicativamente previa, relacionada a la teoría positivista de la (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Linguistic Objectivity in Norm Sentences: Alternatives in Literal Meaning.David Duarte - 2011 - Ratio Juris 24 (2):112-139.
    Assuming that legal science, specifically with regard to interpretation, has to provide the tools to reduce the uncertainty of legal solutions arising from the use of natural languages by legal orders, it becomes a central matter to identify, in this limited domain, the spectrum of semantic variation (and its boundaries) that language brings to the definition of a norm expressed by a norm sentence. It is in this framework that the present paper, analyzing norm sentences as a specific kind of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Hart's and Kelsen's Concepts of Normativity Contrasted.Sylvie Delacroix - 2004 - Ratio Juris 17 (4):501-520.
    Hart's and Kelsen's respective outlooks on the concept of normativity not only differ by the way they explain this concept but also, more importantly, in what they seek to achieve when endeavouring to account for the normative dimension of law. By examining Hart's and Kelsen's models in the light of Korsgaard's understanding of the “normativity problem,” my aim is to emphasise not only their contrasted perspectives, but also the common limit they impose on their theories by dismissing as inappropriate any (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • What are the debates on same-sex marriage and on the recognition of transwomen as women about? On anti-descriptivism and revisionary analysis.Brice Bantegnie - 2020 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 63 (9-10):974-1000.
    ABSTRACT In recent years, debates on same-sex marriage and the recognition of transwomen as women have been raging. These debates often seem to revolve around the meaning of, respectively, the word ‘marriage’ and ‘woman’. That such debates should take place might be puzzling. It seems that if debates on gay and transgender rights revolve around the meaning of these words, then those in favor of same-sex marriage and of the recognition of transwomen as women have no room left to maneuver. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Empire-Building.Brenda M. Baker - 1993 - Dialogue 32 (1):149-.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Principle of Subsidiarity.Stefan Gosepath - 2005 - In Andreas Follesdal & Thomas Pogge (eds.), Real World Justice. Grounds, Principles, Human Rights, and Social Institutions. Springer. pp. 157-170.
  • La tensión entre dos concepciones de los sistemas jurídicos: Estudio en homenaje a Carlos Eduardo Alchourrón.Jorge L. Rodríguez - 2006 - Análisis Filosófico 26 (2):242-276.
    Carlos Eduardo Alchourrón y Eugenio Bulygin efectuaron contribuciones de fundamental importancia para el desarrollo de la teoría de los sistemas jurídicos. Sus ideas evidencian una evolución de la presentación de una visión estática a una visión dinámica de tales sistemas. El objetivo central del presente trabajo consiste en mostrar que existe, no obstante, una cierta tensión en las tesis sostenidas por los autores entre dos concepciones diferentes de los sistemas jurídicos: por una parte, aquella que trata de reconstruir el conjunto (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Commanding and Defining. On Eugenio Bulygin’s Theory of Legal Power-Conferring Rules.Gonzalo Villa Rosas - 2017 - Crítica. Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofía 49 (146):75-105.
    This paper aims to explore two objections raised against Bulygin’s second approach to the definition of the nature of legal power-conferring rules. According to the first objection, such an account is vague about what is defined by legal power-conferring rules qua constitutive rules. I maintain that this vagueness is rooted in the lack of a suitable definition of legal power. I shall be arguing for the reduction of the complexity of the definientia by defining legal power as a species of (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark