Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Computers Are Syntax All the Way Down: Reply to Bozşahin.William J. Rapaport - 2019 - Minds and Machines 29 (2):227-237.
    A response to a recent critique by Cem Bozşahin of the theory of syntactic semantics as it applies to Helen Keller, and some applications of the theory to the philosophy of computer science.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • What did you mean by that? Misunderstanding, negotiation, and syntactic semantics.William J. Rapaport - 2003 - Minds and Machines 13 (3):397-427.
    Syntactic semantics is a holistic, conceptual-role-semantic theory of how computers can think. But Fodor and Lepore have mounted a sustained attack on holistic semantic theories. However, their major problem with holism (that, if holism is true, then no two people can understand each other) can be fixed by means of negotiating meanings. Syntactic semantics and Fodor and Lepore’s objections to holism are outlined; the nature of communication, miscommunication, and negotiation is discussed; Bruner’s ideas about the negotiation of meaning are explored; (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Yes, She Was!: Reply to Ford’s “Helen Keller Was Never in a Chinese Room”.William J. Rapaport - 2011 - Minds and Machines 21 (1):3-17.
    Ford’s Helen Keller Was Never in a Chinese Room claims that my argument in How Helen Keller Used Syntactic Semantics to Escape from a Chinese Room fails because Searle and I use the terms ‘syntax’ and ‘semantics’ differently, hence are at cross purposes. Ford has misunderstood me; this reply clarifies my theory.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Quasi‐Indexicals and Knowledge Reports.William J. Rapaport, Stuart C. Shapiro & Janyce M. Wiebe - 1997 - Cognitive Science 21 (1):63-107.
    We present a computational analysis of de re, de dicto, and de se belief and knowledge reports. Our analysis solves a problem first observed by Hector-Neri Castañeda, namely, that the simple rule -/- `(A knows that P) implies P' -/- apparently does not hold if P contains a quasi-indexical. We present a single rule, in the context of a knowledge-representation and reasoning system, that holds for all P, including those containing quasi-indexicals. In so doing, we explore the difference between reasoning (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Holism, conceptual-role semantics, and syntactic semantics.William J. Rapaport - 2002 - Minds and Machines 12 (1):3-59.
    This essay continues my investigation of `syntactic semantics': the theory that, pace Searle's Chinese-Room Argument, syntax does suffice for semantics (in particular, for the semantics needed for a computational cognitive theory of natural-language understanding). Here, I argue that syntactic semantics (which is internal and first-person) is what has been called a conceptual-role semantics: The meaning of any expression is the role that it plays in the complete system of expressions. Such a `narrow', conceptual-role semantics is the appropriate sort of semantics (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Program Verification and Functioning of Operative Computing Revisited: How about Mathematics Engineering? [REVIEW]Uri Pincas - 2011 - Minds and Machines 21 (2):337-359.
    The issue of proper functioning of operative computing and the utility of program verification, both in general and of specific methods, has been discussed a lot. In many of those discussions, attempts have been made to take mathematics as a model of knowledge and certitude achieving, and accordingly infer about the suitable ways to handle computing. I shortly review three approaches to the subject, and then take a stance by considering social factors which affect the epistemic status of both mathematics (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Ways of reference to Meinongian objects. Ontological commitments of Meinongian theories.Jacek Paśniczek - 1994 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 2 (5):69-86.
    A. Meinong’s views are usually associated with an highly inflated ontology including various kinds of nonexistent objects, incomplete and impossible ones among others. Around the turn of the century B. Russell strongly criticised this ontology accusing it of inconsistency. And perhaps because of this criticism Meinong’s views have been forgotten for a long time. Only recently some philosophers have created theories of objects which are formalisations of Meinong’s ontology or which are directly inspired by the ontology 1 . However there (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Emotie, Perceptie en Cognitie.Magda Michielsens - 1970 - Philosophica 8.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Toward a Framework for Memory : Straus and Some Others.Michael Marsh - 1976 - Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 7 (1):34-54.
    After defining various aspects of memory, this paper has sought to outline the phenomenology of memory developed by Erwin Straus and his effort to refute the trace or engram theory of memory storage. We found Straus proposing some major insights : that human experience has its own structure of lived time, that this experience transcends the realm of physical events, and that the suchness of past experiences is preserved, and can be reactivated, in lived time. Straus's approach repudiates the conventional (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Resonant oscillations of a granular cluster.Evgeniy Khain - 2008 - Complexity 13 (5):45-49.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The many uses of 'belief' in AI.Robert F. Hadley - 1991 - Minds and Machines 1 (1):55-74.
    Within AI and the cognitively related disciplines, there exist a multiplicity of uses of belief. On the face of it, these differing uses reflect differing views about the nature of an objective phenomenon called belief. In this paper I distinguish six distinct ways in which belief is used in AI. I shall argue that not all these uses reflect a difference of opinion about an objective feature of reality. Rather, in some cases, the differing uses reflect differing concerns with special (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Three paradigms of computer science.Amnon H. Eden - 2007 - Minds and Machines 17 (2):135-167.
    We examine the philosophical disputes among computer scientists concerning methodological, ontological, and epistemological questions: Is computer science a branch of mathematics, an engineering discipline, or a natural science? Should knowledge about the behaviour of programs proceed deductively or empirically? Are computer programs on a par with mathematical objects, with mere data, or with mental processes? We conclude that distinct positions taken in regard to these questions emanate from distinct sets of received beliefs or paradigms within the discipline: – The rationalist (...)
    Direct download (13 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Internally generated conscious contents: interactions between sustained mental imagery and involuntary subvocalizations.Hyein Cho, Christine A. Godwin, Mark W. Geisler & Ezequiel Morsella - 2014 - Frontiers in Psychology 5.
  • Involuntary Entry Into Consciousness From the Activation of Sets: Object Counting and Color Naming.Sabrina Bhangal, Christina Merrick, Hyein Cho & Ezequiel Morsella - 2018 - Frontiers in Psychology 9.
  • Energética e hermenêutica: "O problema epistemológico do Freudismo" discutido por Paul Ricoeur.Ricardo Jardim Andrade - 2013 - Prometeus: Filosofia em Revista 6 (12).
    Pode-se considerar como científico o discurso freudiano? Esta é uma questão que tem sido discutida desde os primórdios da psicanálise e recebido por parte de vários estudiosos, notadamente de lógicos, a resposta negativa. Em consonância com tais críticas, alguns teóricos se empenharam para oferecer à psicanálise uma roupagem compatível com as exigências dos lógicos. Os ensaios de releitura do discurso freudiano vêm tanto do interior da psicanálise como do exterior. No primeiro caso, situa-se a tentativa de D. Rapaport de reintegrar (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Minds and Machines.Francis Jeffry Pelletier - unknown
    I was asked to develop a course “Philosophy and Cognitive Science” to be taught for the first time in Spring 1995 in the Philosophy Department at the University of Alberta. Since my cognitive science-related interests are focussed more towards philosophy mixed with artificial intelligence (A I) and linguistics than towards (say) neuroscience or anthropology, I decided to slant the course in t hat direction. The departmental intent was that this should be an upper-level course, but with no spe cific prerequisite (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • To Be and Not To Be.Critical Studies - 1985 - Noûs 19 (2):255-271.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reconsidering the connection between John Stuart Mill and John Rawls.Alan Reynolds - 2013 - Minerva - An Internet Journal of Philosophy 17 (1).
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • To think or not to think.William J. Rapaport - 1988 - Noûs 22 (4):585-609.
    A critical study of John Searle's Minds, Brains and Science (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1984).
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Unsolvable Problems and Philosophical Progress.William J. Rapaport - 1982 - American Philosophical Quarterly 19 (4):289 - 298.
    Philosophy has been characterized (e.g., by Benson Mates) as a field whose problems are unsolvable. This has often been taken to mean that there can be no progress in philosophy as there is in mathematics or science. The nature of problems and solutions is considered, and it is argued that solutions are always parts of theories, hence that acceptance of a solution requires commitment to a theory (as suggested by William Perry's scheme of cognitive development). Progress can be had in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Wyglądy, identyczność i przedmioty nieistniejące.Maciej Sendłak - 2012 - Diametros 31:56-87.
    The article outlines the main motivations for the Guise Theory and its intriguing theses concerning identity, predication, existence, and fiction. The second part of the article is devoted to assessment of Castañeda’s theory. It discusses the most influential critiques of the Guise Theory, as well as (important from a historical point of view) Russell’s objection to theories of nonexistent objects. The last section of the article contains a comparison of the Guise Theory with the Meinong’s Theory of Objects, and points (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What a course on philosophy of computing is not.Vincent C. Müller - 2008 - APA Newsletter on Philosophy and Computers 8 (1):36-38.
    Immanuel Kant famously defined philosophy to be about three questions: “What can I know? What should I do? What can I hope for?” (KrV, B833). I want to suggest that the three questions of our course on the philosophy of computing are: What is computing? What should we do with computing? What could computing do?
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation