Switch to: References

Citations of:

The Just War: Force and Political Responsibility

Rowman & Littlefield Publishers (1991)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Reasonable probability of success as a moral criterion in the western just war tradition.Frances V. Harbour - 2011 - Journal of Military Ethics 10 (3):230-241.
    Abstract Finding the western just war criterion of reasonable chance of success to be a contribution to ethical decision making about armed conflict requires dealing with a number of critiques. Specifying ?probability? rather than the alternatives ?hope? or ?chance?, and raising standards of evidence involved, makes the term less vague. Expanding the concept of ?success? to include morally defensible aims that can be achieved without military victory enriches the understanding of the moral relationship between ends and means in armed conflict. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Just war theory, humanitarian intervention, and the need for a democratic federation.John J. Davenport - 2011 - Journal of Religious Ethics 39 (3):493-555.
    The primary purpose of government is to secure public goods that cannot be achieved by free markets. The Coordination Principle tells us to consolidate sovereign power in a single institution to overcome collective action problems that otherwise prevent secure provision of the relevant public goods. There are several public goods that require such coordination at the global level, chief among them being basic human rights. The claim that human rights require global coordination is supported in three main steps. First, I (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Legacy of Jus Contra Bellum: Echoes of Pacifism in Contemporary Just War Thought.Serena K. Sharma - 2009 - Journal of Military Ethics 8 (3):217-230.
    This article explores the issue of jus contra bellum as a particular development within just war thought. At its heart, the jus contra bellum amounts to an attempt to apply the principles of jus in bello (discrimination and proportionality) in order to negate the jus ad bellum. This approach was rather prevalent throughout the Cold War era, as concerns over the prospective use of nuclear weapons facilitated an increasingly sceptical attitude towards the use of force. Whereas the vast majority of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Responsibility to protect and militarized humanitarian intervention: When and why the churches failed to discern moral Hazard.Esther D. Reed - 2012 - Journal of Religious Ethics 40 (2):308-334.
    This essay addresses moral hazards associated with the emerging doctrine of the Responsibility to Protect (R2P). It reviews the broad acceptance by the Vatican and the World Council of Churches of the doctrine between September 2003 and September 2008, and attempts to identify grounds for more adequate investigation of the moral issues arising. Three themes are pursued: how a changing political context is affecting notions of sovereignty; the authority that can approve or refuse the use of force; and plural foundations (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Proportionate Treatment of Enemy Subjects: A Reformulation of the Principle of Discrimination.Betsy Perabo - 2008 - Journal of Military Ethics 7 (2):136-156.
    This essay argues that the best starting point for discussions of the Principle of Discrimination (PD) is its most basic formulation: In wartime, certain enemy subjects should receive better treatment than others. Other formulations of the PD ? in particular, those centered on the concept of noncombatant immunity ? have sought to identify a single criterion that can be used as the basis for sorting enemy subjects into two (and only two) classes. However, a historical and legal analysis of the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • An Alternative to Pacifism? Feminism and Just-War Theory.Lucinda J. Peach - 1994 - Hypatia 9 (2):152-172.
    Only rarely have feminist theorists addressed the adequacy of just -war theory, a set of principles developed over hundreds of years to assess the justice of going to war and the morality of conduct in war. Recently, a few feminist scholars have found just -war theory inadequate, yet their own counterproposals are also deficient. I assess feminist contributions to just -war theorizing and suggest ways of strengthening, rather than abandoning, this moral approach to war.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • James Turner Johnson's Just War Idea: Commanding the Headwaters of Tradition.Cian O'Driscoll - 2008 - Journal of International Political Theory 4 (2):189-211.
    James Turner Johnson is the foremost scholar of the just war tradition working today. His treatment of the historical development of the just war tradition has been hugely important, influencing a generation of theorists. Despite this, Johnson's work has not generated much in the way of critical commentary or analysis. This paper aims to rectify this oversight. Engaging in a close and critical reading of Johnson's work, it claims that his historical reconstruction of the just war tradition is bounded by (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Nonlethal Weapons, Noncombatant Immunity, and Combatant Nonimmunity: A Study of Just War Theory. [REVIEW]John W. Lango - 2010 - Philosophia 38 (3):475-497.
    Frequently, the just war principle of noncombatant immunity is interpreted as morally prohibiting the intentional targeting of noncombatants. Apparently, many just war theorists assume that to target means to (intend to) kill. Now that effective nonlethal weapons have been envisaged, it should be evident that there is no conceptual connection between intentionally targeting and intentionally killing. For, using nonlethal weapons, there could be intentional targeting without intentional killing. This paper explores the question of whether the noncombatant immunity principle should be (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Impure Agency and the Just War.Rosemary B. Kellison - 2015 - Journal of Religious Ethics 43 (2):317-341.
    Feminist critiques of intention challenge some aspects of traditional just war reasoning, including the criteria of right intention and discrimination. I take note of these challenges and propose some directions just war reasoners might take in response. First, right intention can be evaluated more accurately by judging what actors in war actually do than by attempting to uncover inward dispositions. Assessing whether agents in war have taken due care to minimize foreseeable collateral damage, avoided intentional targeting of noncombatants, corrected previous (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • War, Women, and Political Wisdom: Jean Bethke Elshtain on the Contours of Justice. [REVIEW]J. Daryl Charles - 2006 - Journal of Religious Ethics 34 (2):339 - 369.
    One of the most perceptive and ambidextrous social commentators of our day, Augustinian scholar Jean Bethke Elshtain furnishes in ever fresh ways through her writings a bridge between the ancient and the modern, between politics and ethics, between timeless moral wisdom and cultural sensitivity. To read Elshtain seriously is to take the study of culture as well as the "permanent things" seriously. But Elshtain is no mere moralist. Neither is she content solely to dwell in the domain of the theoretical. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • There's No Deterring the Catholic Bishops.J. Bryan Hehir - 1989 - Ethics International Affairs 3 (1):277-296.
    This article uses two episcopal texts published by the National Conference of Catholic Bishops during the 1980s as a case study of the role of ethics in the foreign policy process.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Humanitarian Intervention after Iraq: Just War and International Law Perspectives.James Turner Johnson - 2006 - Journal of Military Ethics 5 (2):114-127.
  • There's No Deterring the Catholic Bishops.J. Bryan Hehir - 1989 - Ethics and International Affairs 3:277-296.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Pacem in Terris and the just war tradition: A semicentennial reconsideration.David D. Corey & Josh King - 2013 - Journal of Military Ethics 12 (2):142 - 161.
    11 April 2013 marks the 50th anniversary of the papal encyclical, Pacem in Terris, a document that has exerted enormous influence on the doctrines of war and peace articulated by Roman Catholic and non-Catholic writers alike. The argument we make here is that in its understanding of human rights, international peace and philosophical anthropology, the encyclical in effect abandons the ?just war? teachings that had guided the church's view of human conflict for 16 centuries, and we argue that the departure (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • War and intention.Darrell Cole - 2011 - Journal of Military Ethics 10 (3):174-191.
    Abstract Right intention is one of the staple criteria of traditional just war theory. In classical terms, right intention is met when a belligerent aims to achieve a just and peaceful order. I will address the problem of determining when a belligerent has satisfied the criterion of right intention. I will argue that right intention is determined by observing a belligerent's acts during and after a conflict. Intention is not merely a private mental act known ultimately only by the people (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • War, women, and political wisdom.J. Daryl Charles - 2006 - Journal of Religious Ethics 34 (2):341-369.
    ABSTRACT One of the most perceptive and ambidextrous social commentators of our day, Augustinian scholar Jean Bethke Elshtain furnishes in ever fresh ways through her writings a bridge between the ancient and the modern, between politics and ethics, between timeless moral wisdom and cultural sensitivity. To read Elshtain seriously is to take the study of culture as well as the “permanent things” seriously. But Elshtain is no mere moralist. Neither is she content solely to dwell in the domain of the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Perturbations of the soul and pains of the body: Augustine on evil suffered and done in war.Kevin Carnahan - 2008 - Journal of Religious Ethics 36 (2):269-294.
    Many contemporary scholars debate whether war should be conceived as a relative evil or a morally neutral act. The works of Augustine may offer new ways of thinking through the categories of this debate. In an early period, Augustine develops the distinction between evil done and evil suffered. Augustine's early treatments of war locate the saint as detached sage doing only good, and immune from evil suffered. In a middle period, he develops a richer picture of the evil suffered on (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Introduction: The just war tradition and the continuing challenges to world public order.Davis Brown - 2011 - Journal of Military Ethics 10 (3):125-132.
    Abstract This introductory article argues that world public order continues to be challenged by the emergence of the doctrines of anticipatory self-defense and humanitarian intervention. These challenges may be better understood, and reconciled, by application of the just war tradition.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The UN Security Council and the Question of Humanitarian Intervention in Darfur.Alex Bellamy & Paul Williams - 2006 - Journal of Military Ethics 5 (2):144-160.
    This article explores the different moral and legal arguments used by protagonists in the debate about whether or not to conduct a humanitarian intervention in Darfur. The first section briefly outlines four moral and legal positions on whether there is (and should be) a right and/or duty of humanitarian intervention: communitarianism, restrictionist and counter-restrictionist legal positivism and liberal cosmopolitanism. The second section then provides an overview of the Security Council's debate about responding to Darfur's crisis, showing how its policy was (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Ethics of Terror Bombing: Beyond Supreme Emergency.Alex J. Bellamy - 2008 - Journal of Military Ethics 7 (1):41-65.
    Recent years have seen a revival of interest in Michael Walzer's doctrine of ‘supreme emergency’. Simply put, the doctrine holds that, when a state confronts an opponent who threatens annihilation, it can be morally legitimate to violate one of the cardinal rules of the war convention – the principle of non-combatant immunity. Walzer cites the case of Britain's decision to bomb German cities in 1940 as a case in point. Although the theory of supreme emergency has been scrutinised, the historical (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Pacifism.Andrew Fiala - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.