Switch to: References

Citations of:

Mind and Language

Oxford University Press (1975)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Evolutionary Approaches to Epistemic Justification.Helen de Cruz, Maarten Boudry, Johan de Smedt & Stefaan Blancke - 2011 - Dialectica 65 (4):517-535.
    What are the consequences of evolutionary theory for the epistemic standing of our beliefs? Evolutionary considerations can be used to either justify or debunk a variety of beliefs. This paper argues that evolutionary approaches to human cognition must at least allow for approximately reliable cognitive capacities. Approaches that portray human cognition as so deeply biased and deficient that no knowledge is possible are internally incoherent and self-defeating. As evolutionary theory offers the current best hope for a naturalistic epistemology, evolutionary approaches (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Davidson's social externalism.Steven Yalowitz - 1999 - Philosophia 27 (1-2):99-136.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Democracy and pragmatism in curriculum development.J. C. Walker - 1987 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 19 (2):1–10.
  • Skeptical arguments.Jonathan Vogel - 2004 - Philosophical Issues 14 (1):426–455.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Knowledge of language in action.Cheng-Hung Tsai - 2015 - Philosophical Explorations 18 (1):68-89.
    Knowledge of a language is a kind of knowledge, the possession of which enables a speaker to understand and perform a variety of linguistic actions in that language. In this paper, I pursue an agency-oriented approach to knowledge of language. I begin by examining two major agency-oriented models of knowledge of language: Michael Dummett's Implicit Knowledge Model and Jennifer Hornsby's Practical Knowledge Model. I argue that each of these models is inadequate for different reasons. I present an Acquaintance Knowledge Model, (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Quine on matters of fact.David E. Taylor - 2016 - Synthese 193 (2):605-636.
    The idea of there being “no fact of the matter” (NFM) features centrally in Quine’s indeterminacy theses. Yet there has been little discussion of how exactly Quine understands this idea. In this paper I identify, develop and then critically evaluate Quine’s conception of NFM. In Sects. 3–4 I consider a handful of intuitive semantic and ontological conceptions of NFM and argue that none is workable from within Quine’s philosophy. I conclude that the failure of each of these proposals is due (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What every speaker cognizes.Stephen P. Stich - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):39-40.
  • Naturalizing epistemology: Quine, Simon and the prospects for pragmatism.Stephen Stich - 1993 - In C. Hookway & D. Peterson (eds.), Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement. Cambridge University Press. pp. 1-17.
    In recent years there has been a great deal of discussion about the prospects of developing a “naturalized epistemology,” though different authors tend to interpret this label in quite different ways.1 One goal of this paper is to sketch three projects that might lay claim to the “naturalized epistemology” label, and to argue that they are not all equally attractive. Indeed, I’ll maintain that the first of the three – the one I’ll attribute to Quine – is simply incoherent. There (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Reply to Comments.Stephen Schiffer - 1988 - Mind and Language 3 (1):53-63.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Quine’s Eliminativism and the Crystal Spheres.Nathan Stemmer - 2007 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 38 (2):315 - 327.
    Quine’s eliminativist theory has largely been ignored by the philosophical community. This is highly regrettable because Quine’s theory is probably close to correct. Now, the probable correctness of Quine’s theory has an important consequence since, according to the theory, there are no mental entities (events, states, phenomena, properties, etc.) nor do such entities play any role in a scientific account of the relevant phenomena. But the hundreds or probably thousands of publications that deal with issues such as mental causation, the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Quine’s Eliminativism and the Crystal Spheres.Nathan Stemmer - 2007 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 38 (2):315-327.
    Quine’s eliminativist theory has largely been ignored by the philosophical community. This is highly regrettable because Quine’s theory is probably close to correct. Now, the probable correctness of Quine’s theory has an important consequence since, according to the theory, there are no mental entities (events, states, phenomena, properties, etc.) nor do such entities play any role in a scientific account of the relevant phenomena. But the hundreds or probably thousands of publications that deal with issues such as mental causation, the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On universals: an extensionalist alternative to Quine’s resemblance theory. [REVIEW]Nathan Stemmer - 2005 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 38 (1):75 - 90.
    The notion of similarity plays a central role in Quine’s theory of Universals and it is with the help of this notion that Quine intends to define the concept of kind which also plays a central role in the theory. But as Quine has admitted, his attempts to define kinds in terms of similarities were unsuccessful and it is mainly because of this shortcoming that Quine’s theory has been ignored by several philosophers (see, e.g., Armstrong, D. M. (1978a). Nominalism and (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On universals: an extensionalist alternative to Quine’s resemblance theory.Nathan Stemmer - 2007 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 38 (1):75-90.
    The notion of similarity plays a central role in Quine's theory of Universals and it is with the help of this notion that Quine intends to define the concept of kind which also plays a central role in the theory. But as Quine has admitted, his attempts to define kinds in terms of similarities were unsuccessful and it is mainly because of this shortcoming that Quine's theory has been ignored by several philosophers. Nominalism and realism: Universals and Scientific realism. Cambridge: (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Overview of the Book.Stephen Schiffer - 1988 - Mind and Language 3 (1):1-8.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Innate ideas as a naturalistic source of metaphysical knowledge.Steve Stewart-Williams - 2005 - Biology and Philosophy 20 (4):791-814.
    This article starts from the assumption that there are various innate contributions to our view of the world and explores the epistemological implications that follow from this. Specifically, it explores the idea that if certain components of our worldview have an evolutionary origin, this implies that these aspects accurately depict the world. The simple version of the argument for this conclusion is that if an aspect of mind is innate, it must be useful, and the most parsimonious explanation for its (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Hume’s Solution of the Goodman Paradox and the Reliability Riddle.Nathan Stemmer - 2007 - Philosophical Studies 132 (2):137 - 159.
    Many solutions of the Goodman paradox have been proposed but so far no agreement has been reached about which is the correct solution. However, I will not contribute here to the discussion with a new solution. Rather, I will argue that a solution has been in front of us for more than two hundred years because a careful reading of Hume’s account of inductive inferences shows that, contrary to Goodman’s opinion, it embodies a correct solution of the paradox. Moreover, the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hume’s Solution of the Goodman Paradox and the Reliability Riddle.Nathan Stemmer - 2007 - Philosophical Studies 132 (2):137-159.
    Many solutions of the Goodman paradox have been proposed but so far no agreement has been reached about which is the correct solution. However, I will not contribute here to the discussion with a new solution. Rather, I will argue that a solution has been in front of us for more than two hundred years because a careful reading of Hume's account of inductive inferences shows that, contrary to Goodman's opinion, it embodies a correct solution of the paradox. Moreover, the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hume's Two Assumptions.Nathan Stemmer - 1988 - Dialectica 42 (2):93-104.
    One usually speaks of Hume's problem of induction in the singular, as if Hume had called our attention to only one problem which affects the justification of inductive inferences. But Hume shows that this justification depends on two assumptions which are not logically valid. In most studies about the justification of inductive inferences, Hume's approach to base the justification on two assumptions has not been discussed. This seems to have been a mistake, however. Not only do these assumptions play different (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Empiricist versus prototype theories of language acquisition.Nathan Stemmer - 1989 - Mind and Language 4 (3):201-221.
  • Culture, biology, and human behavior.Horst D. Steklis & Alex Walter - 1991 - Human Nature 2 (2):137-169.
    Social scientists have not integrated relevant knowledge from the biological sciences into their explanations of human behavior. This failure is due to a longstanding antireductionistic bias against the natural sciences, which follows on a commitment to the view that social facts must be explained by social laws. This belief has led many social scientists into the error of reifying abstract analytical constructs into entities that possess powers of agency. It has also led to a false nature-culture dichotomy that effectively undermines (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Representation and psychological reality.Elliott Sober - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):38-39.
    In this brief space I want to describe how Chomsky's analysis of "psychological reality" departs from what I think is a fairly standard construal of the idea. This familiar formulation arises from distinguishing between someone's following a rule and someone's acting in conformity with a rule. The former idea, but not the latter, involves the idea that the person has some mental representation of the rule that plays a certain causal role in determining behavior. Although there may be many grammatical (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Virtuous circles.Michael P. Smith - 1987 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 25 (2):207-220.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Stimulus Meaning Reconsidered.Robert Sinclair - 2002 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 40 (3):395-409.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Quine's Naturalized Epistemology and the Third Dogma of Empiricism.Robert Sinclair - 2007 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 45 (3):455-472.
    This essay reconsiders Davidson's critical attribution of the scheme‐content distinction to Quine's naturalized epistemology. It focuses on Davidson's complaint that the presence of this distinction leads Quine to mistakenly construe neural input as evidence. While committed to this distinction, Quine's epistemology does not attempt to locate a justificatory foundation in sensory experience and does not then equate neural intake with evidence. Quine's central epistemological task is an explanatory one that attempts to scientifically clarify the route from stimulus to science. Davidson's (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A Less Radical Interpretation of Davidson and Quine.Robert Sinclair - 2006 - Dialogue 45 (1):107-124.
  • “Plausible insofar as it is intelligible”: Quine on underdetermination.Rogério Passos Severo - 2008 - Synthese 161 (1):141-165.
    Quine’s thesis of underdetermination is significantly weaker than it has been taken to be in the recent literature, for the following reasons: (i) it does not hold for all theories, but only for some global theories, (ii) it does not require the existence of empirically equivalent yet logically incompatible theories, (iii) it does not rule out the possibility that all perceived rivalry between empirically equivalent theories might be merely apparent and eliminable through translation, (iv) it is not a fundamental thesis (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Rules and causation.John R. Searle - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):37-38.
  • Indexicals and the theory of reference.Stephen Schiffer - 1981 - Synthese 49 (1):43--100.
  • An artificial intelligence perspective on Chomsky's view of language.Roger C. Schank - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):35-37.
  • Chomsky's evidence against Chomsky's theory.Geoffrey Sampson - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):34-35.
  • The modularity and maturation of cognitive capacities.David M. Rosenthal - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):32-34.
  • Naturalism radicalized.Javier Rodríguez-alcázar - 1996 - Metaphilosophy 27 (4):356-380.
    In this paper I distinguish two ways of using the expression ‘epistemological naturalism’. In one sense, naturalism amounts to a denial that epistemology should be understood as a kind of first philosophy providing the foundations for science from outside. In a second sense, naturalism holds that human knowledge is a natural phenomenon and that epistemology should be seen as a chapter of natural science. Moreover, naturalism in this second sense usually incorporates some additional specifications that build up a very restrictive (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Cross purposes.Howard Rachlln - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):30-31.
  • On How to Avoid the Indeterminacy of Translation.Panu Raatikainen - 2005 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 43 (3):395-413.
    Quine’s thesis of the indeterminacy of translation has puzzled the philosophical community for several decades. It is unquestionably among the best known and most disputed theses in contemporary philosophy. Quine’s classical argument for the indeterminacy thesis, in his seminal work Word and Object, has even been described by Putnam as “what may well be the most fascinating and the most discussed philosophical argument since Kant’s Transcendental Deduction of the Categories” (Putnam, 1975a: p. 159).
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Reassessing Referential Indeterminacy.Christian Nimtz - 2005 - Erkenntnis 62 (1):1-28.
    Quine and Davidson employ proxy functions to demonstrate that the use of language (behaviouristically conceived) is compatible with indefinitely many radically different reference relations. They also believe that the use of language (behaviouristically conceived) is all that determines reference. From this they infer that reference is indeterminate, i.e. that there are no facts of the matter as to what singular terms designate and what predicates apply to. Yet referential indeterminacy yields rather dire consequences. One thus does wonder whether one can (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • There are many modular theories of mind.Adam Morton - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):29-29.
  • Language: levels of characterisation.John Morton - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):29-30.
  • Chomsky's radical break with modern traditions.Julius M. Moravcsik - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):28-29.
  • Solispsim and subjectivity.A. W. Moore - 1996 - European Journal of Philosophy 4 (2):220-235.
    This essay is concerned with solipsism, understood as the extreme sceptical view that I have no knowledge except of my subjective state. A less rough formulation of the view is mooted, inspired by a Quinean combination of naturalism and empiricism. An objection to the resultant position is then considered, based on Putnam’s argument that we are not brains in vats. This objection is first outlined, then pitted against a series of counter-objections. Eventually it is endorsed, but only at the price (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Indétermination de la traduction et sous-détermination des théories scientifiques.Martin Montminy - 1992 - Dialogue 31 (4):623-.
    La thèse de l'indétermination de la traduction de W. V. O. Quine est certainement une des thèses les plus controversées de la philosophie du langage. Le présent article explique en quoi consiste cette thèse et examine les liens qu'elle entretient avec la thèse de la sous-détermination des théories scientifiques. La première section montre comment la thèse de l'indétermination de la traduction découle de la conception behavioriste du langage de Quine. Les sections suivantes exposent deux façons de dériver la thèse de (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • iTabula si, rasa no!James D. McCawley - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):26-27.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Language learning versus grammar growth.Robert J. Matthews - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):25-26.
  • The new organology.John C. Marshall - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):23-25.
  • Naturalism, scientism and the independence of epistemology.James Maffie - 1995 - Erkenntnis 43 (1):1 - 27.
    Naturalists seek continuity between epistemology and science. Critics argue this illegitimately expands science into epistemology and commits the fallacy of scientism. Must naturalists commit this fallacy? I defend a conception of naturalized epistemology which upholds the non-identity of epistemic ends, norms, and concepts with scientific evidential ends, norms, and concepts. I argue it enables naturalists to avoid three leading scientistic fallacies: dogmatism, one dimensionalism, and granting science an epistemic monopoly.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Intentionality and modern philosophical psychology I: The modern reduction of intentionality.William E. Lyons - 1990 - Philosophical Psychology 3 (2 & 3):247-69.
    In rounded terms and modem dress a theory of intentionality is a theory about how humans take in information via the senses and in the very process of taking it in understand it and, most often, make subsequent use of it in guiding human behaviour. The problem of intentionality in this century has been the problem of providing an adequate explanation of how a purely physical causal system, the brain, can both receive information and at the same time understand it, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • What ever happened to deep structure?George Lakoff - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):22-23.
  • Ende oder Wende der analytischen Philosophie und Wissenschaftstheorie?Dirk Koppelberg - 1981 - Zeitschrift Für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 12 (2):364-400.
    My concern in what follows is to give a comparative report on some important lectures held at the Hegel-Kongreß 1981 in Stuttgart. In discussing the views of Quine, Hacking, Davidson, Putnam and Habermas I want to confront them with some details of Rorty's recent critique of our philosophical tradition. At last I try to give a tentative answer whether there is an end or a turning-point for current analytical philosophy.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Quine on Objects: Realism or Anti-Realism?Antti Keskinen - 2012 - Theoria 78 (2):128-145.
    W. V. Quine describes himself as a “robust realist” about physical objects in the external world. This realism about objects is due to Quine's naturalism. On the other hand, Quine's naturalistic epistemology involves a conception of objects as posits that we introduce in our theories about the world. This conception of objects can be seen as anti-realist rather than realist. In this article, I discuss the questions whether there is a tension between Quine's realism and his epistemological conception of objects, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Spiders in the web of belief: The tangled relations between concepts and theories.Frank C. Keil - 1989 - Mind and Language 4 (1-2):43-50.
  • Reclaiming Quine’s epistemology.Bredo C. Johnsen - 2014 - Synthese 191 (5):1-28.
    Central elements of W. V. Quine’s epistemology are widely and deeply misunderstood, including the following. He held from first to last that our evidence consists of the stimulations of our sense organs, and of our observations, and of our sensory experiences; meeting the interpretive challenge this poses is a sine qua non of understanding his epistemology. He counted both “This is blue” and “This looks blue” as observation sentences. He took introspective reports to have a high degree of certainty. He (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations