Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. A number of questions about a question of number.Alan Garnham - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):350-351.
  • Why study deduction?Kathleen M. Galotti & Lloyd K. Komatsu - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):350-350.
  • Putting sociobiology in its place.Andrew Futterman & Garland E. Allen - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (1):76-77.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Not the module does memory make – but the network.Joaquin M. Fuster - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):631-633.
    This commentary questions the target articles inferences from a limited set of empirical data to support this model and conceptual scheme. Especially questionable is the attribution of internal representation properties to an assembly of cells in a discrete cortical module firing at a discrete attractor frequency. Alternative inferences are drawn from cortical cooling and cell-firing data that point to the internal representation as a broad and specific cortical network defined by cortico-cortical connectivity. Active memory, it is proposed, consists in the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Consciousness is for other people.Chris Frith - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):682-683.
    Gray has expanded his account of schizophrenia to explain consciousness as well. His theory explains neither phenomenon adequately because he treats individual minds in isolation. The primary function of consciousness is to permit high level interactions with other conscious beings. The key symptoms of schizophrenia reflect a failure of this mechanism.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Addiction and embodiment.Ellen Fridland & Corinde E. Wiers - 2018 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 17 (1):15-42.
    Recent experiments have shown that when individuals with a substance use disorder are confronted with drug-related cues, they exhibit an automatically activated tendency to approach these cues. The strength of the drug approach bias has been associated with clinically relevant measures, such as increased drug craving and relapse, and activations in brain reward areas. Retraining the approach bias by means of cognitive bias modification has been demonstrated to decrease relapse rates in patients with an alcohol use disorder and to reduce (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The mental representation of action.Jennifer J. Freyd - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):145-146.
  • The Hebbian paradigm reintegrated: Local reverberations as internal representations.Walter J. Freeman - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):631-631.
    Recurrent excitation is experimentally well documented in cortical populations. It provides for intracortical excitatory biases that linearize negative feedback interactions and induce macroscopic state transitions during perception. The concept of the local neighborhood should be expanded to spatial patterns as the basis for perception, in which large areas of cortex are bound into cooperative behavior with near-silent columns as important as active columns revealed by unit recording.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The ghost is in the other eye: The eidetic image is monocular.David Freides - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (2):295-296.
  • A Thurstonian's reaction to a componential theory of intelligence.John R. Frederiksen - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (4):590-591.
  • On seeking the mythical fountain of consciousness.Jeffrey Foss - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):682-682.
    Because consciousness has an organizational, or functional, center, Gray supposes that there must be a corresponding physical center in the brain. He proposes further that since this center generates consciousness, ablating it would eliminate consciousness, while leaving behavior intact. But the center of consciousness is simply the product of the functional linkages among sensory input, memory, inner speech, and so on, and behavior.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Searle on what only brains can do.J. A. Fodor - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):431-432.
  • How direct is visual perception? Some reflections on Gibson's 'ecological approach'.Jerry A. Fodor & Zenon W. Pylyshyn - 1981 - Cognition 9 (2):139-96.
    Examines the theses that the postulation of mental processing is unnecessary to account for our perceptual relationship with the world, see turvey etal. for a criticque.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   288 citations  
  • Is the human sentence parsing mechanism an ATN?Janet Dean Fodor & Lyn Frazier - 1980 - Cognition 8 (4):417-459.
  • Auditory hallucinations, inner speech, and the dominant hemisphere.Pierre Flor-Henry - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (3):523-524.
  • Speed-insensitive and speed-sensitive strategies in multijoint movements.Tamar Flash - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):215-216.
  • Pulses, bursts, and single-joint movements.Martha Flanders - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):215-215.
  • The Social and Cognitive Dynamics of Paradigmatic Change: A Scientometric Approach.Klaus Fischer - 1992 - Science in Context 5 (1):51-96.
    ArgumentKuhnian phases of paradigmatic development correspond to characteristic variations of citation measures. These correlations can in turn be predicted from a simple model of human information processing when applied to the common environments of scientists. By combining a scientometric and a human information processing approach to the history of scientific thought, structures of disciplinary development, and in particular paradigmatic cycles, can be more reliably assessed than before. Consequently, the quantitative historian of science is liberated to some extent from the vagaries (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Mental models and informal logic.Alec Fisher - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):349-349.
  • Deductive reasoning: What are taken to be the premises and how are they interpreted?Samuel Fillenbaum - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):348-349.
  • The argument for mental models is unsound.James H. Fetzer - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):347-348.
  • Goldman has not defeated folk functionalism.James H. Fetzer - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):42-43.
  • So many models – So little time.Jerome A. Feldman - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):551-552.
  • Learning from instruction.Jerome A. Feldman - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):593-593.
  • On modes of explanation.Rachel Joffe Falmagne - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):346-347.
  • The diversity of the schizophrenias.Raymond Faber - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (3):522-522.
  • The evolutionary aspect of cognitive functions.J. -P. Ewert - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (3):481-483.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On rules, models and understanding.Jonathan St B. T. Evans - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):345-346.
  • Information is in the eye of the beholder.Rhea T. Eskew - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):144-144.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The scientific induction problem: A case for case studies.K. Anders Ericsson - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (3):480-481.
  • Recall or regeneration of past mental states: Toward an account in terms of cognitive processes.K. Anders Ericsson - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):41-42.
  • Representation: A concept that fills no gaps.Robert Epstein - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):377-378.
  • Direct perception or mediated perception: a comparison of rival viewpoints.William Epstein - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):384-385.
  • Mental-model theory and rationality.Pascal Engel - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):345-345.
  • If it looks like a duck, walks like a duck, and quacks like a duck, it is a duck: Neurally mediated responses of the circulation are behavior.Bernard T. Engel - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):307-318.
  • Developing the explanatory dimensions of part–whole realization.Ronald Endicott - 2016 - Philosophical Studies 173 (12):3347-3368.
    I use Carl Gillett’s much heralded dimensioned theory of realization as a platform to develop a plausible part–whole theory. I begin with some basic desiderata for a theory of realization that its key terms should be defined and that it should be explanatory. I then argue that Gillett’s original theory violates these conditions because its explanatory force rests upon an unspecified “in virtue of” relation. I then examine Gillett’s later version that appeals instead to theoretical terms tied to “mechanisms.” Yet (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Conditionality of heart rate responses in healthy subjects and patients with ischemic heart disease.Danguole M. Žemaitytė - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):306-307.
  • Intentionality and information theory.David P. Ellerman - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):143-144.
  • Context and consciousness.Colin G. Ellard - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):681-682.
    The commentary argues that we cannot be sure that human consciousness has survival value and that in order to understand the origins and, perhaps, the function of consciousness, we should examine the behavioural and neural precursors to consciousness in nonhumans. An example is given of research on the role of context in decisions regarding fleeing from probable predators in the Mongolian gerbil.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Consciousness, memory, and the hippocampal system: What kind of connections can we make?Howard Eichenbaum & Neal J. Cohen - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):680-681.
    Gray's account is remarkable in its depth and scope but too little attention is paid to poor correspondences with the literature on hippocampal/subicular damage, the theta rhythm, and novelty detection. An alternative account, focusing on hippocampal involvement in organizing memories in a way that makes them accessible to conscious recollection but not in access to consciousness per se, avoids each of these limitations.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What's wrong with the syntactic theory of mind.M. Frances Egan - 1989 - Philosophy of Science 56 (December):664-74.
    Stephen Stich has argued that psychological theories that instantiate his Syntactic Theory of Mind are to be preferred to content-based or representationalist theories, because the former can capture and explain a wider range of generalizations about cognitive processes than the latter. Stich's claims about the relative merits of the Syntactic Theory of Mind are unfounded. Not only is it false that syntactic theories can capture psychological generalizations that content-based theories cannot, but a large class of behavioral regularities, readily explained by (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Stimulating understanding: Making the example fit the question.Thomas Edelson - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (2):338-339.
  • How representation works is more important than what representations are.Shimon Edelman - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):630-631.
    A theory of representation is incomplete if it states “representations areX” whereXcan be symbols, cell assemblies, functional states, or the flock of birds fromTheaetetus, without explaining the nature of the link between the universe ofXs and the world. Amit's thesis, equating representations with reverberations in Hebbian cell assemblies, will only be considered a solution to the problem of representation when it is complemented by a theory of how a reverberation in the brain can be a representation of anything.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A dualist-interactionist perspective.John C. Eccles - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):430-431.
  • Sociobiology and the problem of culture.John Dupré - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (1):75-76.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The informational character of representations.Fred Dretske - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):376-377.
  • Stalking intentionality.Fred I. Dretske - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):142-143.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Testing sociobiological hypotheses ethnographically.Patricia Draper - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (1):74-75.
  • On Wittgenstein on Cognitive Science.D. Proudfoot - 1997 - Philosophy 72:189-217.
    Cognitive science is held, not only by its practitioners, to offer something distinctively new in the philosophy of mind. This novelty is seen as the product of two factors. First, philosophy of mind takes itself to have well and truly jettisoned the ‘old paradigm’, the theory of the mind as embodied soul, easily and completely known through introspection but not amenable to scientific inquiry. This is replaced by the ‘new paradigm’, the theory of mind as neurally-instantiated computational mechanism, relatively opaque (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The function and process of perception.Jonathan F. Doner & Joseph S. Lappin - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):383-384.